Difference between revisions of "Arguments for the existence of God"

From Conservapedia
Jump to: navigation, search
(Ontological argument: Spelling, grammar, and general cleanup, typos fixed: Anselm’s → Anselm's)
(Alvin Plantinga's modal ontological argument)
(31 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
[[Image:Alphaomega.jpg|thumb|200px|[[God]] is the Alpha and Omega, the first and last, the beginning and the ending <ref>Revelation 22:13</ref>]]
 
'''Arguments for the existence of God''' involve carefully crafted reasoning to demonstrate the undeniable truth that [[God]] exists. See also: [[List of proofs of God]]
 
'''Arguments for the existence of God''' involve carefully crafted reasoning to demonstrate the undeniable truth that [[God]] exists. See also: [[List of proofs of God]]
  
Line 4: Line 5:
  
 
''See also:'' [[Rebuttals to atheist arguments|Common arguments against atheism]]
 
''See also:'' [[Rebuttals to atheist arguments|Common arguments against atheism]]
 
+
[[File:Autumn.jpg|200px|left|thumbnail|The [[argument from beauty]] is a [[teleological argument]].]]
Also known as '''proofs''' for God's existence, these arguments have not always come with full acceptance.  Those opposed to natural theology claim that God's existence cannot be proven by human reason or the natural world, and that any attempt to do so runs the risk of becoming a [[God of the Gaps]] argument.  However, [[Oxford]] scholar Roger Penrose states that [[materialism]] is now the faith of the gaps (see: Atheism of the gaps).<ref>http://www.leaderu.com/ftissues/ft9511/revessay.html</ref>  
+
Also known as [[proof]]s for God's existence, these arguments have not always come with full acceptance.  Those opposed to natural theology claim that God's existence cannot be proven by human reason or the natural world, and that any attempt to do so runs the risk of becoming a [[God of the Gaps]] argument.  However, [[Oxford]] scholar Roger Penrose states that [[materialism]] is now the faith of the gaps (see: Atheism of the gaps).<ref>http://www.leaderu.com/ftissues/ft9511/revessay.html</ref>  
  
 
Viewpoints vary, but responses tend to conclude that God can only be known by supernatural revelation or Scripture alone.  [[Karl Barth]] is a classic example of this as he believed that God is exclusively revealed in [[Jesus Christ]], and Jesus is only revealed in the [[Bible]].  Proponents of natural theology vary as well, but most conclude that the existence of God can be known through human reason although it is not salvific (not a saving knowledge of God).  [[Thomas Aquinas]] is characteristic of this view, holding to the understanding that the created world reflects aspects of its creator that are apparent to all.  Nonetheless, arguments for the existence of God have been formed throughout church history and continue to be used today, namely in the area of [[Christian apologetics]].  
 
Viewpoints vary, but responses tend to conclude that God can only be known by supernatural revelation or Scripture alone.  [[Karl Barth]] is a classic example of this as he believed that God is exclusively revealed in [[Jesus Christ]], and Jesus is only revealed in the [[Bible]].  Proponents of natural theology vary as well, but most conclude that the existence of God can be known through human reason although it is not salvific (not a saving knowledge of God).  [[Thomas Aquinas]] is characteristic of this view, holding to the understanding that the created world reflects aspects of its creator that are apparent to all.  Nonetheless, arguments for the existence of God have been formed throughout church history and continue to be used today, namely in the area of [[Christian apologetics]].  
Line 16: Line 17:
  
 
===Kalam cosmological argument===
 
===Kalam cosmological argument===
 +
[[Image:Billcraig_czvx.jpg‎‎|thumb|150px|[[William Lane Craig]] popularized the Kalam cosmological argument in the [[Western World]]. ]]
 +
 
The aim of this argument is to show that the universe had a beginning in the finite past.  The argument battles against the existence of an [[infinite regression]] of past events which implies a universe that has infinitely existed.  This argument implies the existence of a [[First Cause]].
 
The aim of this argument is to show that the universe had a beginning in the finite past.  The argument battles against the existence of an [[infinite regression]] of past events which implies a universe that has infinitely existed.  This argument implies the existence of a [[First Cause]].
  
Line 24: Line 27:
 
Note that the key phrase here is "''begins'' to exist". The question is not "whatever exists".
 
Note that the key phrase here is "''begins'' to exist". The question is not "whatever exists".
  
The atheistic counter argument has traditionally been to point 2, taking the position that the universe has always existed. It should also be noted that the Kalam argument removes one of the knee jerk reactions to any discussion on creation involving God which is "Then who created God?"  Since God has no beginning, the question becomes meaningless. The Bible makes clear that God exists outside of our construct of time in many locations, including 1 Corinthians 2:7, 2 Timothy 1:9, and Titus 1:2.
+
The atheistic counter argument has traditionally been to point 2, taking the position that the universe has always existed. It should also be noted that the Kalam [[cosmological argument]] removes one of the knee jerk reactions to any discussion on creation involving God which is "Then who created God?"  Since God has no beginning, the question becomes meaningless. The Bible makes clear that God exists outside of our construct of time in many locations, including 1 Corinthians 2:7, 2 Timothy 1:9, and Titus 1:2.
  
===[[Thomism|Thomistic]] cosmological argument===
+
=== Thomistic cosmological argument===
 +
[[Image:Saint Thomas Aquinas.jpg|right|200px|thumb|St. [[Thomas Aquinas]] took the position that [[faith]] and [[reason]] are compatible. ]]
 
# What we observe in this universe is contingent (i.e. dependent, or conditional)
 
# What we observe in this universe is contingent (i.e. dependent, or conditional)
 
# A sequence of causally related contingent things cannot be infinite
 
# A sequence of causally related contingent things cannot be infinite
Line 33: Line 37:
  
 
===Leibnizian cosmological argument===
 
===Leibnizian cosmological argument===
The argument comes from a German polymath, Gottfriend Wilhelm Leibniz.  Leibniz wrote, "The first question which should rightly be asked is this: why is there something rather than nothing?"   
+
The argument comes from a German polymath, [[Gottfried Leibniz|Gottfriend Wilhelm Leibniz]].  Leibniz wrote, "The first question which should rightly be asked is this: why is there something rather than nothing?"   
  
 
The argument runs as follows:
 
The argument runs as follows:
Line 47: Line 51:
  
 
''See also:'' [[Intelligent design]] and [[Anthropic principle]]
 
''See also:'' [[Intelligent design]] and [[Anthropic principle]]
 
+
[[File:Watches have a purpose.png|thumbnail|400px|left|William Paley was an advocate of the [[teleological argument]].
Probably the most popular argument for God's existence is the [[teleological argument]]. Derived from the Greek word ''telos'', which refers to purpose or end, this argument hinges on the idea that the world gives evidence of being designed, and concludes that a divine designer must be posited to account for the orderly world we encounter.  Although the teleological argument dates at least as far back as Plato, it is perhaps most memorable today from the work of [[William Paley]] (1743-1805), in his ''Natural Theology'' (1802). Recently, the teleological argument has gained renewed interest as a core element of the theory of [[Intelligent design|Intelligent Design]] and the related efforts to reconcile science and faith. This was predicted by [[Kelvin]] who pointed out that in the 19th century the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in contemporary zoological speculations and that reaction against frivolities of teleology by 'learned Commentators' on Paley's ''"Natural Theology"'' should have had only a temporary effect in turning attention from ''"the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book"''.<ref>{{cite web |title=On the Origin of Life |author=W. Thomson (Lord Kelvin) |publisher= Transactions of the Geological Society of Glasgow |year=1871 |url=http://zapatopi.net/kelvin/papers/on_the_origin_of_life.html |accessdate=6 June 2015 |quote=I feel profoundly convinced that the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in recent zoological speculations. Reaction against frivolities of teleology, such as are to be found, not rarely, in the notes of learned Commentators on Paley's "Natural Theology," has I believe had a temporary effect in turning attention from the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book. But overpoweringly strong proofs of intelligent and benevolent design lie all round us, and if ever perplexities, whether metaphysical or scientific, turn us away from them for a time, they come back upon us with irresistible force, showing to us through nature the influence of a free will, and teaching us that all living beings depend on one ever-acting Creator and Ruler.}}</ref>   
+
<br />
 +
<br />
 +
One of the most famous statements about the teleological argument using the watchmaker analogy was given by William Paley in his 1802 book ''Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity''.<ref>[http://www.wmcarey.edu/carey/paley/ William Paley - William Carey University]</ref>]]
 +
Probably the most popular argument for God's existence is the [[teleological argument]]. Derived from the Greek word ''telos'', which refers to purpose or end, this argument hinges on the idea that the world gives evidence of being designed, and concludes that a divine designer must be posited to account for the orderly world we encounter.  Although the teleological argument dates at least as far back as Plato, it is perhaps most memorable today from the work of William Paley (1743-1805), in his ''Natural Theology'' (1802). Recently, the teleological argument has gained renewed interest as a core element of the theory of [[Intelligent design|Intelligent Design]] and the related efforts to reconcile science and faith. This was predicted by [[Kelvin]] who pointed out that in the 19th century the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in contemporary zoological speculations and that reaction against frivolities of teleology by 'learned Commentators' on Paley's ''"Natural Theology"'' should have had only a temporary effect in turning attention from ''"the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book"''.<ref>{{cite web |title=On the Origin of Life |author=W. Thomson (Lord Kelvin) |publisher= Transactions of the Geological Society of Glasgow |year=1871 |url=http://zapatopi.net/kelvin/papers/on_the_origin_of_life.html |accessdate=6 June 2015 |quote=I feel profoundly convinced that the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in recent zoological speculations. Reaction against frivolities of teleology, such as are to be found, not rarely, in the notes of learned Commentators on Paley's "Natural Theology," has I believe had a temporary effect in turning attention from the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book. But overpoweringly strong proofs of intelligent and benevolent design lie all round us, and if ever perplexities, whether metaphysical or scientific, turn us away from them for a time, they come back upon us with irresistible force, showing to us through nature the influence of a free will, and teaching us that all living beings depend on one ever-acting Creator and Ruler.}}</ref>   
  
 
Although there are variations, the basic argument goes something like this:
 
Although there are variations, the basic argument goes something like this:
Line 63: Line 70:
 
Research and historical data indicate that a significant portion of [[atheism|atheists]]/agnostics often see the their lives and the world as being the product of purposeful design (see: [[Atheism and purpose]]).<ref>
 
Research and historical data indicate that a significant portion of [[atheism|atheists]]/agnostics often see the their lives and the world as being the product of purposeful design (see: [[Atheism and purpose]]).<ref>
 
*[https://www.nytimes.com/2014/10/19/opinion/sunday/does-everything-happen-for-a-reason.html ''Does everything happen for a reason?''],'' New York Times'', October 17, 2014
 
*[https://www.nytimes.com/2014/10/19/opinion/sunday/does-everything-happen-for-a-reason.html ''Does everything happen for a reason?''],'' New York Times'', October 17, 2014
*[http://creation.com/children-see-the-world-as-designed Children see the world as designed] by  David Catchpoole, [[Creation Ministries International]], Published: 16 July 2009
+
*[https://creation.com/children-see-the-world-as-designed Children see the world as designed] by  David Catchpoole, [[Creation Ministries International]], Published: 16 July 2009
 
*Atheist [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] made the candid confession: "As for me, I don’t see myself as so much dust that has appeared in the world but as a being that was expected, prefigured, called forth. In short, as a being that could, it seems, come only from a creator; and this idea of a creating hand that created me refers me back to God. Naturally this is not a clear, exact idea that I set in motion every time I think of myself. It contradicts many of my other ideas; but it is there, floating vaguely. And when I think of myself I often think rather in this way, for wont of being able to think otherwise." Source: ''Escape from God: The Use of Religion and Philosophy to Evade Responsibility'' By Dean Turner, page 109
 
*Atheist [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] made the candid confession: "As for me, I don’t see myself as so much dust that has appeared in the world but as a being that was expected, prefigured, called forth. In short, as a being that could, it seems, come only from a creator; and this idea of a creating hand that created me refers me back to God. Naturally this is not a clear, exact idea that I set in motion every time I think of myself. It contradicts many of my other ideas; but it is there, floating vaguely. And when I think of myself I often think rather in this way, for wont of being able to think otherwise." Source: ''Escape from God: The Use of Religion and Philosophy to Evade Responsibility'' By Dean Turner, page 109
 
*The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' declares: "In 1885, the Duke of Argyll recounted a conversation he had had with Charles Darwin the year before Darwin's death: In the course of that conversation I said to Mr. Darwin, with reference to some of his own remarkable works on the Fertilization of [[Orchid]]s, and upon The [[Earthworm]]s, and various other observations he made of the wonderful contrivances for certain purposes in nature — I said it was impossible to look at these without seeing that they were the effect and the expression of Mind. I shall never forget Mr. Darwin's answer. He looked at me very hard and said, 'Well, that often comes over me with overwhelming force; but at other times,' and he shook his head vaguely, adding, 'it seems to go away.'(Argyll 1885, 244)[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/teleological-arguments/notes.html Notes to Teleological Arguments for God's Existence]</ref>
 
*The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' declares: "In 1885, the Duke of Argyll recounted a conversation he had had with Charles Darwin the year before Darwin's death: In the course of that conversation I said to Mr. Darwin, with reference to some of his own remarkable works on the Fertilization of [[Orchid]]s, and upon The [[Earthworm]]s, and various other observations he made of the wonderful contrivances for certain purposes in nature — I said it was impossible to look at these without seeing that they were the effect and the expression of Mind. I shall never forget Mr. Darwin's answer. He looked at me very hard and said, 'Well, that often comes over me with overwhelming force; but at other times,' and he shook his head vaguely, adding, 'it seems to go away.'(Argyll 1885, 244)[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/teleological-arguments/notes.html Notes to Teleological Arguments for God's Existence]</ref>
Line 77: Line 84:
  
 
==Anthropological argument==
 
==Anthropological argument==
 +
 +
''See also:'' [[Paleoanthropology]] and [[Bible history]] and [[Biblical archaeology]]
 +
 
The anthropological (anthropos meaning "man") argument is made on the basis of the condition of humanity, of mankind's basic moral standards and the thread a search for a higher being.  It is related to the cosmological and teleological arguments in that it if man has a yearning for God and a conscience when offending him, ostensibly these have their origin and cause in God and not in man.  The argument was perhaps most famously posited by [[Blaise Pascal]], who reasoned that it was better "bet" to believe in God than not to do so.
 
The anthropological (anthropos meaning "man") argument is made on the basis of the condition of humanity, of mankind's basic moral standards and the thread a search for a higher being.  It is related to the cosmological and teleological arguments in that it if man has a yearning for God and a conscience when offending him, ostensibly these have their origin and cause in God and not in man.  The argument was perhaps most famously posited by [[Blaise Pascal]], who reasoned that it was better "bet" to believe in God than not to do so.
  
 
==Ontological argument==
 
==Ontological argument==
The ontological argument attempts to prove God's existence through abstract reasoning alone. The argument is entirely ''[[a priori]],'' i.e. it involves no empirical evidence at all. Rather, the argument begins with an explication of the concept of God, and seeks to demonstrate that God exists on the basis of that concept alone.
+
 
 +
''See also:'' [[Ontological argument]]
 +
[[Image:Anselm.jpg|thumbnail|right|175px|[[Anselm of Canterbury]] was the originator of the ontological argument]]
 +
The [[ontological argument]] attempts to prove God's existence through abstract reasoning alone. The argument is entirely ''[[a priori]],'' i.e. it involves no empirical evidence at all. Rather, the argument begins with an explication of the concept of God, and seeks to demonstrate that God exists on the basis of that concept alone.
 
{{cquote|"The argument is ingenious. It has the appearance of a linguistic trick, but it is a difficult task to say precisely what, if anything, is wrong with it. All forms of the argument make some association between three concepts: the concepts of God, of perfection, and of existence. Very roughly, they state that perfection is a part of the concept of God, and that perfection entails existence, and so that the concept of God entails God's existence." <ref>http://www.philosophyofreligion.info/ontological.html</ref>}}
 
{{cquote|"The argument is ingenious. It has the appearance of a linguistic trick, but it is a difficult task to say precisely what, if anything, is wrong with it. All forms of the argument make some association between three concepts: the concepts of God, of perfection, and of existence. Very roughly, they state that perfection is a part of the concept of God, and that perfection entails existence, and so that the concept of God entails God's existence." <ref>http://www.philosophyofreligion.info/ontological.html</ref>}}
  
Line 88: Line 101:
  
 
===Descartes' ontological argument===
 
===Descartes' ontological argument===
 +
 
We have the idea of an infinitely perfect Being. Since we are finite, and everything around us is finite, the idea of an infinitely perfect Being could not have originated with us or with the nature around us. Therefore, the idea of an infinitely perfect Being must have come from such a being - God.<ref>http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ontological/</ref>
 
We have the idea of an infinitely perfect Being. Since we are finite, and everything around us is finite, the idea of an infinitely perfect Being could not have originated with us or with the nature around us. Therefore, the idea of an infinitely perfect Being must have come from such a being - God.<ref>http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ontological/</ref>
 
Of course, such an idea, is [[shoehorning]] the idea that something must be infinite.
 
Of course, such an idea, is [[shoehorning]] the idea that something must be infinite.
 +
 +
=== Alvin Plantinga's modal ontological argument ===
 +
 +
''See also:'' [[Alvin Plantinga]]
 +
 +
*[https://strangenotions.com/is-the-modal-ontological-argument-for-god-a-sound-proof/ Alvin Plantinga's modal ontological argument (The Introduction)]
  
 
==Free will argument==
 
==Free will argument==
 +
 +
''See also:'' [[Atheism and free will]]
  
 
* There can be no free will in a totally naturalistic system
 
* There can be no free will in a totally naturalistic system
Line 104: Line 126:
 
* In challenging premise 2, those ascribing to [[determinism]] simply believe that free will does not exist and no one has free will.  Therefore, there is no importance to the concept of God.
 
* In challenging premise 2, those ascribing to [[determinism]] simply believe that free will does not exist and no one has free will.  Therefore, there is no importance to the concept of God.
  
==Consciousness==
+
== Argument from Consciousness==
 +
 
 +
''See also:'' [[Atheism and consciousness]] and [[Argument from consciousness]]
 +
[[File:JP Moreland.jpg|thumbnail|170px|right|[[J.P. Moreland]] ]]
 +
The argument from consciousness is an argument for the existence of God based on the problems consciousness poses for the atheistic worldview. The best-known defender of the argument from consciousness is [[J.P. Moreland]].<ref>[http://www.johnpiippo.com/2012/03/argument-from-consciousness-for.html The Argument from Consciousness for the Existence of God] by [[John Piippo]], 3/20/2012</ref> See: [[Atheism and consciousness]]
  
 
* Nature consists of a finite number of elements.
 
* Nature consists of a finite number of elements.
Line 113: Line 139:
 
* Infinite regress of beings is illogical, therefore a single, uncaused causer must be the causer of consciousness.
 
* Infinite regress of beings is illogical, therefore a single, uncaused causer must be the causer of consciousness.
 
* This uncaused causer of the conscience is [[God]]
 
* This uncaused causer of the conscience is [[God]]
 +
 +
Professor [[John Piippo]] on the argument from consciousness:
 +
 +
*[http://www.johnpiippo.com/2012/03/argument-from-consciousness-for.html The Argument from Consciousness for the Existence of God] by [[John Piippo]]
 +
*[http://www.johnpiippo.com/2014/04/one-of-atheisms-irresolvable-problems.html Consciousness: One of Atheism's Irresolvable Problems] by John Piippo
  
 
===Objections===
 
===Objections===
  
* This argument fails to address [[gestalt consciousness]].
+
* [[Evolutionists]] typically argue that consciousness may happen by chance.  However, this is highly illogical and unlikely, so is yet another weak argument for atheism (see: [[Evolution]] and [[Suppression of alternatives to evolution]] and [[Atheism and irrationality]]).  
* [[Evolutionists]] typically argue that consciousness may happen by chance.  However, this is highly illogical and unlikely, so is yet another weak argument for atheism (see: [[Atheism and irrationality]]).  
+
 
* Infinite regress is allowable both in modern mathematics and physics.
 
* Infinite regress is allowable both in modern mathematics and physics.
 
* The last point (that the uncaused causer is God) is unsupported unless it is taken as a statement of definition.  If this is the case, the prior arguments are unnecessary.
 
* The last point (that the uncaused causer is God) is unsupported unless it is taken as a statement of definition.  If this is the case, the prior arguments are unnecessary.

Revision as of 13:33, November 21, 2019

God is the Alpha and Omega, the first and last, the beginning and the ending [1]

Arguments for the existence of God involve carefully crafted reasoning to demonstrate the undeniable truth that God exists. See also: List of proofs of God

Overview

See also: Common arguments against atheism

Also known as proofs for God's existence, these arguments have not always come with full acceptance. Those opposed to natural theology claim that God's existence cannot be proven by human reason or the natural world, and that any attempt to do so runs the risk of becoming a God of the Gaps argument. However, Oxford scholar Roger Penrose states that materialism is now the faith of the gaps (see: Atheism of the gaps).[2]

Viewpoints vary, but responses tend to conclude that God can only be known by supernatural revelation or Scripture alone. Karl Barth is a classic example of this as he believed that God is exclusively revealed in Jesus Christ, and Jesus is only revealed in the Bible. Proponents of natural theology vary as well, but most conclude that the existence of God can be known through human reason although it is not salvific (not a saving knowledge of God). Thomas Aquinas is characteristic of this view, holding to the understanding that the created world reflects aspects of its creator that are apparent to all. Nonetheless, arguments for the existence of God have been formed throughout church history and continue to be used today, namely in the area of Christian apologetics.

These arguments do not generally tell us much about God, and certainly not the details that is revealed in the Bible. Rather, they argue for the basics, such that God[3] exists, although some characteristics of God can be deduced from the nature of His creation.

Cosmological arguments

See also: Atheism and the origin of the universe and Cosmological argument

Kalam cosmological argument

William Lane Craig popularized the Kalam cosmological argument in the Western World.

The aim of this argument is to show that the universe had a beginning in the finite past. The argument battles against the existence of an infinite regression of past events which implies a universe that has infinitely existed. This argument implies the existence of a First Cause.

The form of the argument is:

  1. Whatever begins to exist has a cause.
  2. The universe began to exist.
  3. Therefore, the universe has a cause.

Note that the key phrase here is "begins to exist". The question is not "whatever exists".

The atheistic counter argument has traditionally been to point 2, taking the position that the universe has always existed. It should also be noted that the Kalam cosmological argument removes one of the knee jerk reactions to any discussion on creation involving God which is "Then who created God?" Since God has no beginning, the question becomes meaningless. The Bible makes clear that God exists outside of our construct of time in many locations, including 1 Corinthians 2:7, 2 Timothy 1:9, and Titus 1:2.

Thomistic cosmological argument

St. Thomas Aquinas took the position that faith and reason are compatible.
  1. What we observe in this universe is contingent (i.e. dependent, or conditional)
  2. A sequence of causally related contingent things cannot be infinite
  3. The sequence of causally dependent contingent things must be finite

Conclusion: There must be a first cause in the sequence of contingent causes

Leibnizian cosmological argument

The argument comes from a German polymath, Gottfriend Wilhelm Leibniz. Leibniz wrote, "The first question which should rightly be asked is this: why is there something rather than nothing?"

The argument runs as follows:

  1. Every existing thing has an explanation of its existence, either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause.
  2. If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is God.
  3. The universe is an existing thing.
  4. Therefore, the explanation of the universe is God.

Some atheists object to premise 2 in that God does not have to be the explanation, but that the universe can be what is called a necessary being (one which exists of its own nature and have no external cause). This was a suggestion of David Hume who demanded, "Why may not the material universe be the necessarily existent being?" (Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part 9). The Kalam Cosmological Argument is helpful. If Hume (and other atheists) is right in saying that the universe is a necessary being/thing, then this implies that the universe is eternal. This is exactly what the Kalam argument seeks to disprove. Thus, the Kalam is a valuable supplement to the Leibnizian argument.

Teleological argument

See also: Intelligent design and Anthropic principle

William Paley was an advocate of the teleological argument.

One of the most famous statements about the teleological argument using the watchmaker analogy was given by William Paley in his 1802 book Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity.[4]

Probably the most popular argument for God's existence is the teleological argument. Derived from the Greek word telos, which refers to purpose or end, this argument hinges on the idea that the world gives evidence of being designed, and concludes that a divine designer must be posited to account for the orderly world we encounter. Although the teleological argument dates at least as far back as Plato, it is perhaps most memorable today from the work of William Paley (1743-1805), in his Natural Theology (1802). Recently, the teleological argument has gained renewed interest as a core element of the theory of Intelligent Design and the related efforts to reconcile science and faith. This was predicted by Kelvin who pointed out that in the 19th century the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in contemporary zoological speculations and that reaction against frivolities of teleology by 'learned Commentators' on Paley's "Natural Theology" should have had only a temporary effect in turning attention from "the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book".[5]

Although there are variations, the basic argument goes something like this:

  1. X is too complex to have occurred randomly or naturally.
  2. Therefore, X must have been created by an intelligent being, Y.
  3. God is that intelligent being.
  4. Therefore, God exists.

Often, X is life, but there are other values for which the argument works. For example, scientists have found that if the universal constants (such as the speed of light or the Planck constant) were only a tiny bit different life could not exist.

A significant portion of atheists see their lives and the world being the product of design

Research and historical data indicate that a significant portion of atheists/agnostics often see the their lives and the world as being the product of purposeful design (see: Atheism and purpose).[6]

Comments on the teleological argument

The first and second premises assume that one can infer the existence of intelligent design merely by examining an object. This is the same principle that archaeology uses to determine if, for example, a piece of stone is a stone tool.

The teleological argument assumes that because life is complex, it must have been designed. This is based on observations that complexity is not the outcome of random processes. Some object that life or objects are described as, “orderly” or “ordered”, and that this implies that an intelligent designer has ordered them. These objector claim that a system can be non-random or ordered simply because it is following impersonal physical processes, for example diamonds or snowflakes. However, such "ordered" systems do not have complexity, which life has.

The third premise is rejected by some even if the first and second premises are accepted, as the implied designer (Y) might be an unknown force or mere demiurge, not God as God is commonly understood. It is argued in defense that the outside force through which Y came into being might then be explained as a more powerful being resulting in either an omnipotent being or infinite regression.

Critics often argue that the teleological argument would apply to the designer, arguing any designer must be at least as complex and purposeful as the designed object. This, they say, would create the absurdity of an infinite series of designers. However, the counter-argument of an "undesigned designer," akin to Aristotle's uncaused causer, is common. Furthermore, it has been argued that God is not complex, that is, He is not composed of many interrelated parts, so the complexity argument does not apply. However, such a response would refute itself, for how could something simple create something complex, intelligently?

Anthropological argument

See also: Paleoanthropology and Bible history and Biblical archaeology

The anthropological (anthropos meaning "man") argument is made on the basis of the condition of humanity, of mankind's basic moral standards and the thread a search for a higher being. It is related to the cosmological and teleological arguments in that it if man has a yearning for God and a conscience when offending him, ostensibly these have their origin and cause in God and not in man. The argument was perhaps most famously posited by Blaise Pascal, who reasoned that it was better "bet" to believe in God than not to do so.

Ontological argument

See also: Ontological argument

Anselm of Canterbury was the originator of the ontological argument

The ontological argument attempts to prove God's existence through abstract reasoning alone. The argument is entirely a priori, i.e. it involves no empirical evidence at all. Rather, the argument begins with an explication of the concept of God, and seeks to demonstrate that God exists on the basis of that concept alone.

"The argument is ingenious. It has the appearance of a linguistic trick, but it is a difficult task to say precisely what, if anything, is wrong with it. All forms of the argument make some association between three concepts: the concepts of God, of perfection, and of existence. Very roughly, they state that perfection is a part of the concept of God, and that perfection entails existence, and so that the concept of God entails God's existence." [7]

The ontological argument was first formulated by Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109), one of the great medieval philosopher-theologians, in his Proslogium, Chapter 2. Anselm's ontological argument rests on the identification of God as “that than which no greater can be conceived”. Once it is understood that God is that of which no greater can be conceived, Anselm suggests, it becomes evident that God must exist.

A problem with this argument is that it merely defines God into existence. It is unclear if the concept of being able to conceive of a perfect being has any connection to actual existence. Without being able to make this connection, the merit of the argument can become questionable.

Descartes' ontological argument

We have the idea of an infinitely perfect Being. Since we are finite, and everything around us is finite, the idea of an infinitely perfect Being could not have originated with us or with the nature around us. Therefore, the idea of an infinitely perfect Being must have come from such a being - God.[8] Of course, such an idea, is shoehorning the idea that something must be infinite.

Alvin Plantinga's modal ontological argument

See also: Alvin Plantinga

Free will argument

See also: Atheism and free will

  • There can be no free will in a totally naturalistic system
  • Free will exists
  • Therefore, God exists

Oxygen and hydrogen don't 'choose' to combine, they do so due to natural laws. In a naturalistic system every component that makes us up obeys similar natural laws. The concept of freewill or choice would therefore not exist.

Objections

Some challenge this argument on the basis that premises one and two have not been proven. They argue:

  • In challenging premise 1, those ascribing to compatibilism believe that our experience of free will is still compatible with naturalistic causes even if the mechanism that causes this to be is not yet known and no viable explanation can be postulated apart from acting as if it is so.[9] Since this can not be disproven, it is possible that free will exists in a naturalistic system.
  • In challenging premise 2, those ascribing to determinism simply believe that free will does not exist and no one has free will. Therefore, there is no importance to the concept of God.

Argument from Consciousness

See also: Atheism and consciousness and Argument from consciousness

The argument from consciousness is an argument for the existence of God based on the problems consciousness poses for the atheistic worldview. The best-known defender of the argument from consciousness is J.P. Moreland.[10] See: Atheism and consciousness

  • Nature consists of a finite number of elements.
  • We (our physical bodies) consist of those elements.
  • The elements themselves which we consist of, and nature itself, have no consciousness.
  • Despite our elements themselves having no consciousness, we do.
  • Consciousness can not happen by chance, therefore there must be a being who supply that to us.
  • Infinite regress of beings is illogical, therefore a single, uncaused causer must be the causer of consciousness.
  • This uncaused causer of the conscience is God

Professor John Piippo on the argument from consciousness:

Objections

  • Evolutionists typically argue that consciousness may happen by chance. However, this is highly illogical and unlikely, so is yet another weak argument for atheism (see: Evolution and Suppression of alternatives to evolution and Atheism and irrationality).
  • Infinite regress is allowable both in modern mathematics and physics.
  • The last point (that the uncaused causer is God) is unsupported unless it is taken as a statement of definition. If this is the case, the prior arguments are unnecessary.

Argument from beauty

For a more detailed treatment, see Argument from beauty.

The argument from beauty argues the existence of beauty in the natural world testifies to the existence of God who both designed natural beauty and who possesses a divine beauty.

Resources

  • God, Are you There? Five Reasons God Exists and Three Reasons it Makes a Difference, by William Lane Craig (from the RZIM Critical Questions Booklet Series)
  • Does God Exist? The Debate between Theists and Atheists, by J.P. Moreland (theist) and Kai Nielsen (atheist). Prometheus Books, 1993.

See also

References

  • This article is based off the Theopedia.com article which is in the public domain.
  1. Revelation 22:13
  2. http://www.leaderu.com/ftissues/ft9511/revessay.html
  3. The term "God" is a reference to the ultimate being, not necessarily the Christian God. There term is here capitalised as it is a reference to the ultimate being, not a counterfeit or lesser "god-like" being.
  4. William Paley - William Carey University
  5. W. Thomson (Lord Kelvin) (1871). On the Origin of Life. Transactions of the Geological Society of Glasgow. Retrieved on 6 June 2015. “I feel profoundly convinced that the argument of design has been greatly too much lost sight of in recent zoological speculations. Reaction against frivolities of teleology, such as are to be found, not rarely, in the notes of learned Commentators on Paley's "Natural Theology," has I believe had a temporary effect in turning attention from the solid and irrefragable argument so well put forward in that excellent old book. But overpoweringly strong proofs of intelligent and benevolent design lie all round us, and if ever perplexities, whether metaphysical or scientific, turn us away from them for a time, they come back upon us with irresistible force, showing to us through nature the influence of a free will, and teaching us that all living beings depend on one ever-acting Creator and Ruler.”
    • Does everything happen for a reason?, New York Times, October 17, 2014
    • Children see the world as designed by David Catchpoole, Creation Ministries International, Published: 16 July 2009
    • Atheist Jean-Paul Sartre made the candid confession: "As for me, I don’t see myself as so much dust that has appeared in the world but as a being that was expected, prefigured, called forth. In short, as a being that could, it seems, come only from a creator; and this idea of a creating hand that created me refers me back to God. Naturally this is not a clear, exact idea that I set in motion every time I think of myself. It contradicts many of my other ideas; but it is there, floating vaguely. And when I think of myself I often think rather in this way, for wont of being able to think otherwise." Source: Escape from God: The Use of Religion and Philosophy to Evade Responsibility By Dean Turner, page 109
    • The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy declares: "In 1885, the Duke of Argyll recounted a conversation he had had with Charles Darwin the year before Darwin's death: In the course of that conversation I said to Mr. Darwin, with reference to some of his own remarkable works on the Fertilization of Orchids, and upon The Earthworms, and various other observations he made of the wonderful contrivances for certain purposes in nature — I said it was impossible to look at these without seeing that they were the effect and the expression of Mind. I shall never forget Mr. Darwin's answer. He looked at me very hard and said, 'Well, that often comes over me with overwhelming force; but at other times,' and he shook his head vaguely, adding, 'it seems to go away.'(Argyll 1885, 244)Notes to Teleological Arguments for God's Existence
  6. http://www.philosophyofreligion.info/ontological.html
  7. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ontological/
  8. "The Astonishing Hypothesis is that "You," your joys and your sorrows, your memories and your ambitions, your sense of personal identity and free will, are in fact no more than the behavior of a vast assembly of nerve cells and their associated molecules ... Free Will is located in or near the anterior cingulate sulcus." Francis Crick, The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for the Soul, Charles Scribner's Sons, New York, NY, 1993, p. 3, 268.
  9. The Argument from Consciousness for the Existence of God by John Piippo, 3/20/2012

External links

Multimedia

ApologeticsPress.org (RealPlayer)