Changes

Jump to: navigation, search

Niccolò Machiavelli

116 bytes added, 15:24, March 10, 2017
/* External links */ Recat
[[Image:Nicolo.jpg|right|thumb|250px|Portrait of Machiavelli by Santi di Tito.]]'''Niccolò Machiavelli''' (May 3, 1469 – June 21, 1527), was the leading political theorist of the [[Renaissance]] and one of the best nonfiction writers in all of Italian literature. A politician and writer based in [[Florence]], he is best known for his book ''[[The Prince]]'', which showed how a self-serving ruler will follow the policy that the "end justifies the means," whereby a ruler can gain power (the "means") in any deceitful or unjust manner possible in order to achieve his often undisclosed goals (the "end"). During his time and long afterward, Machiavelli was considered to have been inspired by the devil, and his name has been used for centuries to describe the use or approval of unscrupulous, self-serving political action. ''The Prince'' made '''"Machiavellian"''' a byword for deceit, despotism and political manipulation, as in a politician who spends all his time and effort on obtaining and retaining power for himself.
'''Niccolò Was Machiavelli''' (May 3, 1469 – June 21, 1527), was the leading political theorist of the [[Renaissance]] and one of the best nonfiction writers in all of Italian literature. A politician and writer based in [[Florence]], he a Machiavellian? The question much debated by scholars is best known for his book whether Machiavelli intended ''The Prince'', which showed to be an actual guide book in how to be a self-serving ruler will follow the policy that the "end justifies the meansruthless tyrant," whereby or—as most scholars argue—wrote it as a ruler can gain power (warning to citizens. While the "means") book was written in any deceitful or unjust manner possible in order to achieve his often undisclosed goals (the "end"). During his time and long afterwardform of a guide for princes, Machiavelli there was considered to have been inspired no actual prince involved, unlike guide books written by others. For that matter, no tyrant has ever needed the devilbook to get ideas how to oppress people. On the other hand, good citizens do need a guide to evil so that they can recognize it and his name has been used fight back to keep their institutions, distrust politicians, and keep watch for centuries corruption. Machiavelli, most scholars believe, was dedicated to describe republicanism as the use or approval best form of unscrupulous, self-serving political actiongovernment and opposed tyranny. ''The Prince'' made '''"Machiavellian"''' was a byword for deceit, despotism and political manipulation, as in a politician who spends all his time and effort on obtaining and retaining power for himselfwarning that it could happen like this if citizens let down their guard.
Was Machiavelli In other books he took an opposite view, emphasizing that when a state does not have a prince (a Machiavellian? The question much debated by scholars is whether Machiavelli intended king), the people must have civic virtue. In ''The PrinceDiscourses on Livy'' to be an actual guide book in how to be Machiavelli has been a ruthless tyrant, or--as most scholars argue--wrote it as a warning to republican citizensmajor positive influence of modern conservative thought through his impact on civic humanism. While He took the book was written lead in the form defining what civic virtue means for a citizen of a guide for princes, there was no actual prince involved, unlike all republic—a state where the other guide books written by otherspeople are sovereign and not some king. For that matterexample, no tyrant a citizen has ever needed the book duty to get ideas how to oppress people. On the other hand good citizens do need a guide to evil so that they can recognize it oppose corruption and when called upon fight back to keep their republican institutions, distrust politicians, and keep watch for corruptionhis country. MachiavelliHis ideas strongly influenced British, most scholars believeFrench and American thought on the duties of the good citizen, was dedicated to republicanism as and can be traced through American history from the best form days of government [[Benjamin Franklin]] and opposed tyranny[[James Madison]] down to the 21st century.<ref>Paul A. Rahe, ed. ''The PrinceMachiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy' was a warning that it could happen like this if citizens let down their guard.' (2005)</ref>
In other books he took an opposite view, emphasizing that when a state does not have a Prince (a king), the people must have civic virtue. In ''Discourses on Livy'' Machiavelli has been a major positive influence of modern conservative thought through his impact on [[civic humanism]]. He took the lead in defining what civic virtue means for a citizen of a republic--a state where the people are sovereign and not some king. For example a citizen has the duty to oppose corruption and when called upon fight for his country. His ideas on [[republicanism]] strongly influenced British, French and American thought on the duties of the good citizen, and can be traced through American history from the days of [[Benjamin Franklin]] and [[James Madison]] down to the 21st century.<ref>Paul A. Rahe, ed. ''Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy'' (2005)</ref>
==Biography==
Machiavelli's father was a Florentine lawyer of moderate means, who came from an old and noble family. He supervised the superb humanistic education the boy received in the classics, literature, philosophy, and law.
From the age of 20-29 he worked in Rome, employed in the banking business. In 1498 Machiavelli was elected to the Florentine chancery ("civil service," in modern terms), as secretary and second chancellor. The city deliberately gave preference for top positions to well-educated humanists, even more than experience or political connections. He was the staff aide to the Ten of War, the committee responsible for Florence's foreign and diplomatic relations. He acted as secretary to its ambassadors and drafted detailed reports on foreign affairs. He served until 1512, when the Spanish overthrew the Republic.
He married Marietta Corsini in 1501, who bore him six children, and suffered his infidelities with patience; she . She outlived him by a quarter of a century.
Machiavelli devoted himself with single-minded intensity to the grueling and poorly paid service of the Republic. In 1507 he added the role of chancellor of the Nove di Milizia (Nine of the Militia), a magistracy he fought to create because Florence needed a citizen army. He argued that putting every citizen in arms was much better than using mercenary troops which, he said, were largely responsible for the military weakness of most Italian states. He did create and train a citizen army, but it did poorly in battle in 1512.
Italy was a scene of intense political conflict involving four dominant city-states (Florence, Milan, Venice, and Naples), along with the [[Papacy, history|Papacy]], [[France, history|France]], Spain, and the Holy Roman Empire.
When Machiavelli was growing up Florence was under the control of [[Lorenzo de ' Medici]]. Italy was invaded in 1494 by Charles VIII of France, who forced the [[Medici]] family to flee. A republic was established but it immediately came under the dictatorship of religious fanatic [[Girolamo Savonarola]]. The people turned against the monk and executed him in 1498.[[File:Niccolo Machiavelli Uffizi.jpg|left|280px]]Machiavelli was a trusted advisor adviser to the head of the republic, Piero Soderini, who sent him on numerous diplomatic missions. Although he never had decisive authority, Machiavelli's missions often proved to be of considerable delicacy and importance. They included visits to several courts. In 1500 he spent six months at the court of [[Louis XII]] of France, to find out the terms on which the king would help Florence fight its war against the rebellious subject-city of Pisa. Florence depended on its powerful ally to maintain its independence against powerful foes, but France thought Florence was a poorly governed, small weak state.<ref> Skinner, ''Machiavelli'' (2000) pp 8-9</ref>
He spent some four months at the court of [[Cesare Borgia]] (1475-1507), the aggressive young Spanish duke who kept seizing territories across Italy and demanded an alliance with Florence. The duke went out of his way to expound his policies and the ambitions underlying them and Machiavelli was greatly impressed. The duke, he reported, is "superhuman in his courage", as well as being a man of grand designs, who "thinks himself capable of attaining anything he wants". Moreover, his actions are no less striking than his words, for he "controls everything by himself", governs "with extreme secrecy", and decides and executes his plans with devastating suddenness. Machiavelli saw that Borgia was no mere upstart but someone who "must now be regarded as a new power in Italy." Borgia was the most ruthless prince in Italy and became the model for ''The Prince.''<ref> Skinner, ''Machiavelli'' (2000) p. 11</ref>
At Rome, in 1503, he kept an eye on the election of a new pope ([[Julius II]]); and at the court of the Holy Roman Emperor Maximilian in 1507 he discussed the terms of a payment which the Emperor had demanded from Florence. Borgia, Machiavelli noted in ''The Prince'' ch 7, put excessive confidence in his own "fortune" (luck), was outmaneuvered by Pope Julius II, and expelled from Italy. Machiavelli, who strongly disliked the political power of the Church, suggests Borgia should have destroyed the papacy in order to stay in power.<ref> See Scott and Sullivan (1994).</ref> Most historians agree he was very hostile to organized Christianity and profoundly anti-Christian because it made men humble, unmanly, and feeble. Christianity, he concluded::"Has glorified more humble and contemplative men rather than men of action. It also places the highest good in humility, lowliness, and contempt of human things: the [Roman pagan philosophy] places it in the greatness of soul, the strength of body, and all the other things which make men very brave."<ref> ''Discourses'' [http://www.constitution.org/mac/disclivy2.htm#2:02 book 2 chapter 2, online]</ref>
{{cquote|Has glorified more humble and contemplative men rather than men of action. It also places the highest good in humility, lowliness, and contempt of human things: the [Roman pagan philosophy] places it in the greatness of soul, the strength of body, and all the other things which make men very brave.<ref>''Discourses'' [http://www.constitution.org/mac/disclivy2.htm#2:02 book 2 chapter 2, online]</ref>}}  However, there is a dissent that suggests he really sought to reform the Church.<ref> For the minority view see Sebastian de Grazia, [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0679743421/ref=sib_dp_srch_bod?v=search-inside&keywords=christianity&go.x=0&go.y=0&go=Go%21# ''Machiavelli in Hell'' (1989) page 115 online ] </ref>
Machiavelli was an unusually keen observer. In writing his books during retirement he incorporated verbatim into the ''Discourses'' and especially ''The Prince,'' the evaluations, and even the epigrams, that he prepared as a working diplomat.
''The Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livius'' is Machiavelli's fullest discussion on his views on the practice of politics and government, and on the theories that should guide that practice. It was written in the same period as his more well known work, ''The Prince'' (1513-1519 approx.) The latter is a brief handbook on for the use of rulers, the former is an extended commentary on the first ten of thirty five books that remain of Livy's History of Rome, making him an important classical scholar in addition to his contributions to political philosophy.
Machiavelli's ''Discourses,'' is the work of a staunch republican. It advises citizens of a republic how to preserve their liberty and avoid corruption. He concludes that self-government is the best guarantee of security and prosperity, noting that the interests of the people and the politicians are often antithetical, and that citizens should have a healthy distrust of politicians. The voice of the people he likens to the voice of God.<ref> See Femia (2004), pp 11-12, 69</ref>
===Military strategy===
''The Art of War'' is the first major work on modern military thought, as the world's first systematic treatise on military strategy.<ref>Although the Greeks invented military history, and the Chinese were famous for collections of aphorisms. European military thought was most influenced by Machiavelli. Peter Peret et al, eds. ''Makers of Modern Strategy: From Machiavelli to the Nuclear Age'' (1986), esp. ch 1 by Felix Gilbert, "Machiavelli".</ref> His only major book that appeared before Machiavelli's death. its seven volumes examines military strategy and the relationship between war and politics.<ref>Christopher Lynch, in Introduction to ''Art of War'' (2003) p. xiii</ref>.
Italy could not be freed by hiring soldiers because: :"Mercenaries and auxiliaries are useless and dangerous. And if a prince holds on to his state by means of mercenary armies, he will never be stable or secure; for they are disunited, ambitious, without discipline, disloyal; they are brave among friends; among enemies they are cowards; they have no fear of God, they keep no faith with men; and your downfall is deferred only so long as the attack is deferred; and in peace you are plundered by them, in war by your enemies. The reason for this is that they have no other love nor other motive to keep them in the field than a meager wage, which is not enough to make them want to die for you. They love being your soldiers when you are not making war, but when war comes they either flee or desert.<ref> ''The Prince'' ch 12. Florence indeed had a bad experience but most historians feel that in general the mercenary system usually worked effectively. Skinner, ''Machiavelli'' (2000) p 36. </ref>
Allies were not much better{{cquote|Mercenaries and auxiliaries are useless and dangerous. And if a prince holds on to his state by means of mercenary armies, he will never be stable or secure; forthey are disunited, "the arms ambitious, without discipline, disloyal; they are brave among friends; among enemies they are cowards; they have no fear of another man either slide off God, they keep no faith with men; and your backdownfall is deferred only so long as the attack is deferred; and in peace you are plundered by them, weigh in war by your enemies. The reason for this is that they have no other love nor other motive to keep them in the field than a meager wage, which is not enough to make them want to die for you down. They love being your soldiers when you are not making war, but when war comes they either flee or tie you updesert." <ref> ''The Prince'' ch 1312. Florence indeed had a bad experience but most historians feel that in general the mercenary system usually worked effectively. Skinner, ''Machiavelli'' (2000) p 36.</ref>}}
Allies were not much better, for, "the arms of another man either slide off your back, weigh you down, or tie you up."<ref>''The Prince'' ch 13</ref> Machiavelli was the great promoter of the citizens' militia. He organized the first one in Florence and examined it in detail, concluding that the defence of a republic depended on the fighting ability and willingness of its citizens. Hired armies or mercenaries, he concluded, could not defend freedom. His ideas influenced the British "County Party" and the Americans before 1776 as they prepared to use their militias to defend freedom.<ref> Gilbert, "Machiavelli" in Paret, ed. ''Makers of Modern Strategy'' pp. 19-22</ref>
===The Prince===
The [[Middle Ages]] saw many books of advice for princes, all of which explained that to be successful the prince had to lead a virtuous life. Machiavelli explained that in the real world it was just the opposite. The virtuous got trampled and the vicious won out, especially if they covered their tracks. "Hence it is necessary for a prince wishing to hold his own to know how to do wrong, and to make use of it or not according to necessity."<ref> ''The Prince'' ch. 15</ref>
As for personal integrity:
:"Every one admits how praiseworthy it is in a prince to keep faith, and to live with integrity and not with craft. Nevertheless our experience has been that those princes who have done great things have held good faith of little account, and have known how to circumvent the intellect of men by craft, and in the end have overcome those who have relied on their word....But it is necessary to know well how to disguise this characteristic....Therefore it is unnecessary for a prince to have all the good qualities I have enumerated, but it is very necessary to appear to have them."<ref> ''The Prince'' ch. 18</ref>
Machiavelli uses "virtù" to refer to the range of personal qualities, such as ruthlessness and the flexibility to rapidly respond to changing circumstances regardless of past promises, that the prince will need to keep in power and achieve great results. However, this "virtù" has nothing in common with moral virtue.
The ''The Prince'' advocated desperate measures for a desperate situation; Machiavelli's ridiculed half-measures and his dramatic statements and antithesis combined to produce bold and startling generalizations. Politics, he argued, is an art that is independent of morality and religion in its necessary methods. He has often been charged with cynicism for trying to discover permanently valid rules for political behavior based on observation of how men do in fact behave rather than on moral evaluation of how they ought to behave. That is, he advocated "realism" rather than "idealism" as a research technique in political science.
Machiavelli discovered the laws of politics by observing diplomacy firsthand and studying history --from history—from what he called his "long experience of modern affairs and continuous study of the ancient world." However, scholars have concluded that he was not actually empirical; he formed conclusions first then sought out examples in history.
At the end ''The Prince'' appeals urgently for strong leadership to create a powerful native state and free Italy from foreign domination. To free Italy required ruthless action, he argued.
Machiavelli was not thoroughly consistent. Some contradictions include the a despairing view of the nature of man coupled with a fervent belief in the ability of a leader possessed of virtù to liberate Italy from foreign domination; this with the backing of the people, despite former evidences of the people's corruptibility.
 
===History of Florence===
The ''History of Florence'' (1925) displayer's dramatic power as the patriotic reader is swept along from the origins of Italian medieval civilization to the threshold of the French invasions at the end of the 15th century. He is harshly critical of the negative role of the Catholic Church --that Church—that is, the papacy.
The major themes in ''History of Florence'' are the necessity of basing strong government on ultimate consent, and the inevitable corruption of the state if it tolerates political factions. As a scholar Machiavelli relied heavily on the details as related by earlier chroniclers, but he shaped and combined his material with the purpose of discovering the true causes of historical events as revealed by the psychology of individual persons and the conflicting interests of classes; he used history to provide lessons which he thought remained permanently valid. He was one of the first historians to ignore the role of divine intervention in shaping history, a mark of his commitment to [[Humanism]].
==Contributions to Political Philosophypolitical philosophy==
Machiavelli was in many respects not an innovator. His largest political work seeks to bring back a rebirth of the Ancient [[Roman Republic]]; its values, virtues and principles the ultimate guiding authority of his political vision. Machiavelli is essentially a restorer of something old and forgotten. The [[republicanism]] he focused on, especially the theme of civic virtue, became one of the dominant political themes of the modern world, and was a central part of the foundation of [[Republicanism|American political values]].
Machiavelli studied the way people lived and aimed to inform leaders how they should rule and even how they themselves should live. To an extent he admits that the old tradition was true - men are obliged to live virtuously as according to [[Aristotle]]s [[Virtue Ethics]] principle. However, he denies that living virtuously necessarily leads to happiness. Machiavelli viewed misery as ''one of the vices that enables a prince to rule'' <ref>Leo Strauss, Joseph Cropsey, ''History of Political Philosophy'' (Chicago, 1987) p. 300</ref> Machiavelli states boldly in The Prince, ''The answer is, of course, that it would be best to be both loved and feared. But since the two rarely come together, anyone compelled to choose will find greater security in being feared than in being loved.'' <ref>Niccolò Machiavelli, ''The Prince'', p. 60</ref> In much of Machiavelli's work, it seems that the ruler must adopt unsavory policies for the sake of the continuance of his regime.
Hans Baron was the most influential scholar to study Machiavelli. Najemy (1996) examines Baron's ambivalent portrayal, arguing that Baron tended to see Machiavelli simultaneously as the cynical debunker and the faithful heir of civic humanism. By the mid-1950s, Baron had come to consider civic humanism and Florentine republicanism as early chapters of a much longer history of European political liberty, a story in which Machiavelli and his generation played a crucial role. This conclusion led Baron to modify his earlier negative view of Machiavelli. He tried to bring the Florentine theorist under the umbrella of civic humanism by underscoring the radical differences between ''The Prince'' and the ''Discourses'' and thus revealing the fundamentally republican character of the ''Discourses''. However, Baron's inability to come to terms with Machiavelli's harsh criticism of early 15th-century commentators such as Leonardo Bruni ultimately prevented him from fully reconciling Machiavelli with civic humanism. Pocock (1981) traces the Machiavellian belief in and emphasis upon Greco-Roman ideals of unspecialized civic virtue and liberty from 15th century Florence through 17th century England and Scotland to 18th century America. Thinkers who shared these ideals tended to believe that the function of property was to maintain an individual's independence as a precondition of his virtue. Consequently, in the last two times and places mentioned above, they were disposed to attack the new commercial and financial regime that was beginning to develop. However, Paul Rahe (1992) takes issue with Pocock on the origins and argues Machiavelli's republicanism was not rooted in antiquity but was is entirely novel and modern. Scholars have argued that [[James Madison]] followed Machiavelli's republicanism when he set up the [[Jeffersonian Republicans]] in 1792, a party opposed to [[Alexander Hamilton]] and the [[Federalist Party|Federalists]].<ref>Gary Rosen in Rahe, ed. ''Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy'' (2005) [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0521851874/ref=sib_dp_pop_toc?ie=UTF8&p=S008#reader-link p. 231 online]</ref> Conservative historians likewise conclude that [[Thomas Jefferson]]'s republicanism was "deeply in debt" to Machiavelli, whom he praised.<ref>Rahe, ''Jefferson's Machiavellian Political Science'' in Rahe, ed. ''Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy'' (2005) [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0521851874/ref=sib_dp_pt#reader-link p. 209 online]</ref>
Pocock (1981) traces the Machiavellian belief in and emphasis upon Greco-Roman ideals of unspecialized civic virtue and liberty from 15th-century Florence through 17th-century England and Scotland to 18th-century America. Thinkers who shared these ideals tended to believe that the function of property was to maintain an individual's independence as a precondition of his virtue. Consequently, in the last two times and places mentioned above, they were disposed to attack the new commercial and financial regime that was beginning to develop. However, Paul Rahe (1992) takes issue with Pocock on the origins and argues Machiavelli's republicanism was not rooted in antiquity but was is entirely novel and modern. Scholars have argued that [[James Madison followed Machiavelli's republicanism when he (and Jefferson) set up the [[Democratic-Republican Party]] in the 1790s to oppose what they saw as the emerging aristocracy that they feared [[Alexander Hamilton]] was creating with the [[Federalist Party]].<ref> Gary Rosen in Rahe, ed. ''Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy'' (2005) [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0521851874/ref=sib_dp_pop_toc?ie=UTF8&p=S008#reader-link p. 231 online]</ref> Conservative historians likewise conclude that [[Thomas Jefferson]]'s republicanism was "deeply in debt" to Machiavelli, whom he praised.<ref> Rahe, ''Jefferson's Machiavellian Political Science'' in Rahe, ed. ''Machiavelli's Liberal Republican Legacy'' (2005) [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0521851874/ref=sib_dp_pt#reader-link p. 209 online] </ref>
===Realist or evil?===
For four centuries scholars have debated whether Machiavelli was the theorist of evil, or just being realistic. ''The Prince'', made the word "Machiavellian" a byword for deceit, despotism and political manipulation. Some historians argue Machiavelli had a secret (or very subtle) message that explains away the ugly implications of the plain text, saying that Machiavelli really favored virtue after all and was just trying to trick princes into policies that would lead to their overthrow, not their triumph.<ref>John Langton and Mary G. Deitz, "Machiavelli's Paradox: Trapping or Teaching the Prince" ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 81, No. 4 (Dec., 1987), pp. 1277-1288 [http://www.jstor.org/pss/1962589 at JSTOR] </ref>
[[Leo Strauss]], the American neo-conservative, denounces him as a "teacher of evil," because he counsels the princes to avoid the values of justice, mercy, temperance, wisdom, and love of their people in preference to the use of cruelty, violence, fear, and deception.<ref> Leo Strauss, [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0226777022/ref=sib_dp_srch_bod?v=search-inside&keywords=teacher+of+evil&go.x=16&go.y=8 ''Thoughts on Machiavelli'' (1957), p 9 online] </ref> Italian anti-fascist philosopher Benedetto Croce (1925) concludes Machiavelli is simply a "realist" or "pragmatist" who accurately states that moral values in reality do not greatly affect the decisions that political leaders make.<ref> Benedetto Croce, [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/1406739774/ref=sib_books_pg?ie=UTF8&keywords=Benedetto%20Croce%20machiavelli&p=S02H&checkSum=%252FombMxeAC6hIVUToYvbv9hivFP6U3vxoUdbCmtPQco4%253D ''My Philosophy'' (1949), p. 142 online]</ref> German philosopher Ernst Cassirer (1946) held that Machiavelli simply adopts the stance of a political scientist—-a Galileo of politics--in politics—in distinguishing between the "facts" of political life and the "values" of moral judgment.<ref> Ernst Cassirer, [http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0300000367/ref=sib_dp_srch_bod?v=search-inside&keywords=machiavelli+galileo ''The Myth of the State,'' (1946) p.136, online]</ref>
===Thoughts on the State===
The Founding Fathers read Machiavelli closely. In his ''Defence of the Constitutions of Government of the United States,'' Adams praised Machiavelli, with Algernon Sidney and [[Montesquieu]], as a philosophic defender of mixed government. For Adams, Machiavelli restored empirical reason to politics, while his analysis of factions was commendable. Adams likewise agreed with the Florentine that human nature was immutable and driven by passions. He also accepted Machiavelli's belief that all societies were subject to cyclical periods of growth and decay. For Adams, Machiavelli lacked only a clear understanding of the institutions necessary for good government.<ref>C. Bradley Thompson, "John Adams's Machiavellian Moment," ''Review of Politics'' 1995 57(3): 389-417, in [[EBSCO]]</ref>
Most recently, [[Michael A. Ledeen]], holder of the "Freedom Chair" at the conservative [[American Enterprise Institute]], was instrumental in uniting neoconservatives with the new Christian Right. An admirer of the political philosophy of Machiavelli,<ref> Michael Ledeen, ''Machiavelli on Modern Leadership; Why Machiavelli's Iron Rules are as Timely and Important Today as Five Centuries'' (1999)</ref>, he used Christian fundamentalism as a political tool to advance the candidacy and help ground the presidency of George W. Bush, producing what political scientist David Domke has called "political fundamentalism." Ledeen's theoretical ideas have influenced the policies of [[Dick Cheney]], [[Donald Rumsfeld]], [[Paul Wolfowitz]] and [[Karl Rove]].<ref>Ledeen appeared over seventy times on [[Pat Robertson]]'s televised 700 Club, promoting the Neoconservatives' political plan for the Middle East before an audience of several million evangelical viewers. Hugh B.Urban, "Machiavelli Meets the Relgious Right: Michael Ledeen, the Neoconservatives, and the Political Uses of Fundamentalism," ''Journal of Ecumenical Studies'' 2007 42(1): 76-97,</ref> ==See also==* [[Humanism]]* [[Republicanism]]* [[Machiavellianism]]* [[The Prince]]
==References==
See the more detailed guide in the Bibliography below
* Bondanella, Peter, and Mark Musa, eds. ''The Portable Machiavelli'' (1979)
* Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in ''Cambridge Modern History'' (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp 190-218 190–218 [http://books.google.com/books?id=d7kFAAAAIAAJ&pg=RA3-PA720&dq=Burd++Machiavelli+intitle:Cambridge+intitle:Modern+intitle:History&lr=&num=30&as_brr=0#PRA1-PA190,M1 online edition]
* de Grazia, Sebastian. ''Machiavelli in Hell'' (1989), highly favorable intellectual biography; won the Pulitzer Prize [http://www.amazon.com/Machiavelli-Hell-Sebastian-Grazia/dp/0679743421/ref=sr_1_1?ie=UTF8&s=books&qid=1208471341&sr=8-1 excerpt and text search]
* Jensen, De Lamar, ed. ''Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist?'' (1960) essays by scholars [http://www.questia.com/read/34624137?title=Machiavelli%3a%20Cynic%2c%20Patriot%2c%20or%20Political%20Scientist%3f online edition]
* Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction'' (2000) [http://www.questia.com/read/22093813?title=Machiavelli%3a%20A%20Very%20Short%20Introduction online edition], good place to start
* Viroli, Maurizio. ''Niccolo's Smile: A Biography of Machiavelli'' (2000) [http://www.amazon.com/Niccolos-Smile-Machiavelli-Maurizio-Viroli/dp/0374221871/ref=sr_1_6?ie=UTF8&s=books&qid=1199685890&sr=8-6 excerpt and text search]
* Viroli, Maurizio. ''Machiavelli'' (1998) 252pp[http://www.questia.com/read/23271960?title=Machiavelli online edition]
=Bibliography=
==Biographies==
* Burd, L. A., "Florence (II): Machiavelli" in ''Cambridge Modern History'' (1902), vol. I, ch. vi. pp 190-218 190–218 [http://books.google.com/books?id=d7kFAAAAIAAJ&pg=RA3-PA720&dq=Burd++Machiavelli+intitle:Cambridge+intitle:Modern+intitle:History&lr=&num=30&as_brr=0#PRA1-PA190,M1 online Google edition]* de Grazia, Sebastian. ''Machiavelli in Hell'' (1989), highly favorable intellectual biography; won the Pulitzer Prize; difficult and not the place to start[http://www.amazon.com/Machiavelli-Hell-Sebastian-Grazia/dp/0679743421/ref=sr_1_1?ie=UTF8&s=books&qid=1208471341&sr=8-1 excerpt and text search]
* Hale, J. R. ''Machiavelli and Renaissance Italy'' (1961) [http://www.questia.com/read/10359207?title=Machiavelli%20and%20Renaissance%20Italy online edition]
* Hulliung, Mark. ''Citizen Machiavelli'' (1983)
* Ridolfi, Roberto. ''The Life of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (1963), a standard scholarly biography
* Schevill, Ferdinand. ''Six Historians'' (1956), pp. 61-91&nbsp;61–91
* Skinner, Quentin. ''Machiavelli: A Very Short Introduction'' (2000) [http://www.questia.com/read/22093813?title=Machiavelli%3a%20A%20Very%20Short%20Introduction online edition]
* Villari, Pasquale. ''The Life and Times of Niccolò Machiavelli'' (2 vol 1892), good older biography; [http://books.google.com/books?id=SvzZ51e1ktsC&printsec=frontcover&dq=intitle:machiavelli+inauthor:Pasquale+inauthor:Villari&lr=&num=30&as_brr=0 online Google edition vol 1]; [http://books.google.com/books?id=Jv0FN8fOEHIC&printsec=frontcover&dq=intitle:machiavelli+inauthor:Pasquale+inauthor:Villari&lr=&num=30&as_brr=0#PPP2,M1 online Google edition vol 2]
==Political thought==
* Arciniegas, Germán. "Savonarola, Machiavelli, and Guido Antonio Vespucci: Totalitarian and Democrat 500 Years Ago," ''Political Science Quarterly,'' (1954) 69:184-201, argues that modern totalitarianism is a blending of Machiavelli's theories and Savonarola's techniques of rabble rousing. [http://www.jstor.org/pss/2145082 in JSTOR]
* Ball, Terence. "The Picaresque Prince: Reflections on Machiavelli and Moral Change," ''Political Theory,'' Vol. 12, No. 4 (Nov., 1984), pp. 521-536 &nbsp;521–536 [http://www.jstor.org/pss/191497 in jstor]
* Baron, Hans. ''The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance: Civic Humanism and Republican Liberty in an Age of Classicism and Tyranny'' (2 vol 1955), highly influential, deep study of civic humanism (republicanism); 700 pp. [http://books.google.com/books?id=PC0oFzJpFBwC&printsec=frontcover&dq=intitle:crisis+intitle:early+inauthor:hans+inauthor:baron&lr=&num=30&as_brr=0&sig=tw7r_LsDJ0cDz66H4WSylNz3TA0 excerpts and text search]; [http://hdl.handle.net/2027/heb.01379 ACLS E-books]; also [http://hdl.handle.net/2027/heb.01379 vol 2 in ACLS E-books]
* Baron, Hans. ''In Search of Florentine Civic Humanism'' (2 vols. 1988).
* Baron Hans, "Machiavelli: The Republican Citizen and the Author of The Prince" in ''The English Historical Review'' 76 (1961), pp. 217-53&nbsp;217–53. [http://www.jstor.org/pss/557541 in JSTOR]
* Bock, Gisela; Skinner, Quentin; and Viroli, Maurizio, ed. ''Machiavelli and Republicanism.'' (1990). 316 pp. [http://www.amazon.com/Machiavelli-Republicanism-Ideas-Context-Gisela/dp/0521435897/ref=sr_1_1?ie=UTF8&s=books&qid=1199685240&sr=8-1 excerpt and text search]
* Butterfield, Herbert. ''The Statecraft of Machiavelli'' (1940).
* Chabod, Federico''Machiavelli & the Renaissance'' (1958) [http://www.questia.com/read/56380461?title=Machiavelli%20%26%20the%20Renaissance online edition]; [http://hdl.handle.net/2027/heb.01383 online from ACLS E-Books]
* Colish, Marcia L. "Republicanism, Religion, and Machiavelli's Savonarolan Moment," ''Journal of the History of Ideas,'' Vol. 60, No. 4 (Oct., 1999), pp. 597-616 &nbsp;597–616 [http://www.jstor.org/pss/3654110 in JSTOR]* Colish, Marcia L. "Machiavelli's Art of War: A Reconsideration," ''Renaissance Quarterly'', Vol. 51, No. 4 (Winter, 1998), pp. 1151-1168 &nbsp;1151–1168 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/2901963 in JSTOR]* Fischer, Markus. "Machiavelli's Political Psychology," ''The Review of Politics,'' Vol. 59, No. 4 (Autumn, 1997), pp. 789-829 &nbsp;789–829 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/1408308 in JSTOR]
* Gilbert, Felix. ''Machiavelli and Guicciardini: Politics and History in Sixteenth-Century Italy'' (2nd ed. 1984) [http://hdl.handle.net/2027/heb.01706 online from ACLS-E-books]
* Gilbert, Felix. "Machiavelli: The Renaissance of the Art of War," in Edward Mead Earle, ed. ''The Makers of Modern Strategy'' (1944)
* Jensen, De Lamar, ed. ''Machiavelli: Cynic, Patriot, or Political Scientist?'' (1960) essays by scholars [http://www.questia.com/read/34624137?title=Machiavelli%3a%20Cynic%2c%20Patriot%2c%20or%20Political%20Scientist%3f online edition]
* Lukes, Timothy J. "Lionizing Machiavelli," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 95, No. 3 (Sep., 2001), pp. 561-575 &nbsp;561–575 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/3118233 in JSTOR]* Lukes, Timothy J. "Martialing Machiavelli: Reassessing the Military Reflections," ''The Journal of Politics,'' Vol. 66, No. 4 (Nov., 2004), pp. 1089-1108 &nbsp;1089–1108 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/3449530 in JSTOR]
* Femia, Joseph V. ''Machiavelli Revisited'' (2004) [http://www.questia.com/read/111592064?title=Machiavelli%20Revisited online edition], 140pp, good place to start
* McCormick, John P. "Machiavelli against Republicanism: On the Cambridge School's 'Guicciardinian Moments,'" ''Political Theory'', Vol. 31, No. 5 (Oct., 2003), pp. 615-643 &nbsp;615–643 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/3595689 in JSTOR]
* Mansfield, Harvey C. ''Machiavelli's New Modes and Orders: A Study of the Discourses on Livy'' (2001) [http://www.amazon.com/Machiavellis-New-Modes-Orders-Discourses/dp/0226503704/ref=sr_1_10?ie=UTF8&s=books&qid=1199685890&sr=8-10 excerpt and text search]
* Mansfield, Harvey C. '' Machiavelli's Virtue'' (1996), 371pp
* Mansfield, Harvey C. "Machiavelli's Political Science," ''The American Political Science Review,'' Vol. 75, No. 2 (Jun., 1981), pp. 293-305 &nbsp;293–305 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/1961365 in JSTOR]* Mindle, Grant B. "Machiavelli's Realism," ''The Review of Politics,'' Vol. 47, No. 2 (Apr., 1985), pp. 212-230 &nbsp;212–230 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/1406671 in JSTOR]
* Najemy, John M. "Baron's Machiavelli and Renaissance Republicanism." ''American Historical Review'' 1996 101(1): 119-129. ISSN 0002-8762 Fulltext [http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0002-8762(199602)101%3A1%3C119%3ABMARR%3E2.0.CO%3B2-5 in Jstor].
* Nederman, Cary J. "Amazing Grace: Fortune, God, and Free Will in Machiavelli's Thought," ''Journal of the History of Ideas'' 60: 617-638. [http://www.jstor.org/stable/3654111 in JSTOR]
* Parel, A. J. "The Question of Machiavelli's Modernity," ''The Review of Politics,'' Vol. 53, No. 2 (Spring, 1991), pp. 320-339 &nbsp;320–339 [http://www.jstor.org/stable/1407757 in JSTOR]
* Pellerin, Daniel. "Machiavelli's Best Fiend." ''History of Political Thought'' 2006 27(3): 423-453. Issn: 0143-781x on Pope Alexander VI
* Pocock, J.G.A. ''The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition'' (1975; new ed. 2003), a highly influential study of ''Discourses'' and its vast influence; [http://www.amazon.com/Machiavellian-Moment-Florentine-Political-Republican/dp/0691114722/ref=sr_1_1?ie=UTF8&s=books&qid=1199685548&sr=8-1 excerpt and text search]; also [http://www.questia.com/read/100774068?title=The%20Machiavellian%20Moment%3a%20Florentine%20Political%20Thought%20and%20the%20Atlantic%20Republican%20Tradition online 1975 edition]
* [http://oll.libertyfund.org/index.php?option=com_staticxt&staticfile=show.php%3Fperson=3801&Itemid=28 full text books from the Liberty Fund, a conservative think tank]
==External links==
* [https://librivox.org/author/885 Works by Niccolò Machiavelli - text and free audio] - [[LibriVox]]
==See also==* [[Humanism]]* [[Republicanism]]* [[Machiavellianism]]{{DEFAULTSORT:Machiavelli, Niccolò}}
[[Category:Italian Authors|Machiavelli, Niccolo]]
[[Category:Renaissance]]
[[Category:Historians]]
[[Category:Political Theory]]
[[Category:Republicanism]]
 {{DEFAULTSORT[[Category:Machiavelli, Niccolò}}Featured articles]]
Block, SkipCaptcha, edit
1,942
edits