Difference between revisions of "Real number"

From Conservapedia
Jump to: navigation, search
(Fix many things; more to come)
(What is the problem? Aren't rational numbers good enough?: Spelling/Grammar Check, typos fixed: less then → less than)
(10 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{Math-m}}
 
{{Math-m}}
  
The '''real numbers''' are a set of numbers with extremely important theoretical and practical properties.  They can be considered the numbers used for ordinary measurement of physical things like length, area, weight, charge, etc.  They are the 4<sup>th</sup> item in this hierarchy of types of [[number]]s:
+
The '''real numbers''' are a set of numbers with extremely important theoretical and practical properties.  They can be considered to be the numbers used for ordinary measurement of physical things like length, area, weight, charge, etc.  Mathematicians denote the set of real numbers with an ornate capital letter: <math>\mathbb{R}</math>.  They are the 4th item in this hierarchy of types of [[number]]s:
  
 
*The "[[natural number]]s", 1, 2, 3, ...  (There is controversy about whether zero should be included.  It doesn't matter.)
 
*The "[[natural number]]s", 1, 2, 3, ...  (There is controversy about whether zero should be included.  It doesn't matter.)
Line 7: Line 7:
 
*The "[[rational number]]s", or [[fraction]]s, like 355/113
 
*The "[[rational number]]s", or [[fraction]]s, like 355/113
 
*The "real numbers", including irrational numbers
 
*The "real numbers", including irrational numbers
*The "[[complex number]]s, which give solutions to polynomial equations
+
*The "[[complex number]]s", which give solutions to polynomial equations
  
 
Real numbers are typically represented by a decimal (or any other base) representation, as in 3.1416.  It can be shown that any decimal representation that either terminates or gets into an endless repeating pattern is rational.  The other numbers are real numbers that are ''irrational''.  Examples are <math>\sqrt{10} = 3.162277660168...\,</math> and <math>\pi = 3.1415926535...\,</math>.  These decimal representations neither repeat nor terminate.
 
Real numbers are typically represented by a decimal (or any other base) representation, as in 3.1416.  It can be shown that any decimal representation that either terminates or gets into an endless repeating pattern is rational.  The other numbers are real numbers that are ''irrational''.  Examples are <math>\sqrt{10} = 3.162277660168...\,</math> and <math>\pi = 3.1415926535...\,</math>.  These decimal representations neither repeat nor terminate.
 +
 +
__TOC__
  
 
==Formal definition==
 
==Formal definition==
  
Formally, real numbers are defined as the unique [[Field (mathematics)|field]] which is [[ordered]], [[Complete (mathematics)|complete]], and [[Archimedean]]. The reals can be constructed from the [[rationals]] by means of [[Dedekind cut]]s or [[Cauchy sequence]]s, i.e. it is the completion of the [[metric space]] of rational numbers.
+
Formally, real numbers are defined as the unique [[Field (mathematics)|field]] which is [[ordered]], [[Complete (mathematics)|metrically complete]], and [[Archimedean]]. The reals can be constructed from the rationals by means of [[Dedekind cut]]s or [[Cauchy sequence]]s, as outlined below.
  
 
==Real line==
 
==Real line==
  
The real numbers can be thought of as a [[line]], called the '''real line'''. Each real number represents a point on the real line. However, it is a mistake to think of the real line as a row of individual points, like beads. There is no real number “just to the right” of a given real number. This is because the real numbers, like the rational numbers, are a [[dense set]], so points accumulate around each other.<ref>http://abstractmath.org/MM/MMRealNumbers.htm</ref>
+
The real numbers can be thought of as a [[line]], called the '''real line'''. Each real number represents a point on the real line. <!-- [This is unnecessary and misleading.  Mentioning it at all can lead people into wrong thinking that they wouldn't otherwise do.  Just don't say it.  And I have no idea what "points accumulate around each other" means.  In any case, the reference covers this, if anyone cares.]  However, it is a mistake to think of the real line as a row of individual points, like beads. There is no real number “just to the right” of a given real number. This is because the real numbers, like the rational numbers, are a [[dense set]], so points accumulate around each other.--><ref>http://abstractmath.org/MM/MMRealNumbers.htm</ref>
  
 
The real line is useful as a [[coordinate system]] for [[graph]]ing [[functions]]. Thus, the [[x-axis]] and [[y-axis]] are both instances of the real line. The real line is the basis for geometric [[measurement]]s, and more generally for ideas in [[metric topology]].
 
The real line is useful as a [[coordinate system]] for [[graph]]ing [[functions]]. Thus, the [[x-axis]] and [[y-axis]] are both instances of the real line. The real line is the basis for geometric [[measurement]]s, and more generally for ideas in [[metric topology]].
 +
 +
==What is the problem?  Aren't rational numbers good enough?==
 +
 +
Any real-world measurement that anyone could possibly make, one can make as accurately as one wants with rational numbers.  For example, one can calculate the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter to within one part is a trillion using the number 3.1415926535898 (<math>\pi\,</math> itself is irrational.)  Put another way, you never have to worry about the difference between the rationals and the reals in a lumber yard or a laboratory.  The technical term that topologists use for this state of affairs is that the rationals are [[dense subset|dense]].
 +
 +
The shortcoming of the rationals, that is overcome by defining the reals, is a somewhat subtle theoretical point.  The most direct example is that, if one lived in a world with only rational numbers, 2 has no square root, even though it obviously should have one.
 +
 +
::One can easily prove that there is no rational number m/n such that (m/n)<sup>2</sup> = 2.  The factors of m<sup>2</sup> all come in pairs, as do the factors of n<sup>2</sup>.  But the factors of m<sup>2</sup> must be the same as the factors of n<sup>2</sup> except for a single extra factor of 2.
 +
 +
The theoretical property that the rational numbers lack is called the ''least upper bound'' property.
 +
 +
:Definition:  A number B is an ''upper bound'' for a set of numbers if no element of the set is greater than B.  (There is also the notion of a lower bound.)
 +
 +
For example, 10 is an upper bound for the open interval <math>(3, 6)\,</math>.  7 is also an upper bound, as is 6.  5 is not.  2 is a lower bound.
 +
 +
Some sets do not have upper bounds.  For example, all rational or real numbers, or all odd integers.
 +
 +
:Definition:  A number L is a ''least upper bound'' (often abbreviated "lub") if it is an upper bound and no other upper bound is smaller.  (There is also the notion of a greatest lower bound, abbreviated "glb".)  6 is the lub of the open interval <math>(3, 6)\,</math>.  3 is its glb.  6 and 3 are also the lub and glb of the closed interval <math>[3, 6]\,</math>&mdash;the inclusion of the endpoints makes no difference.
 +
 +
::The least upper bound is also sometimes called the "supremum", abbreviated "sup".  The greatest lower bound is also sometimes called the "infimum", abbreviated "inf".
 +
 +
A set has the ''least upper bound property'' if every set that has an upper bound has a least upper bound.  There is also a ''greatest lower bound property'', and any reasonable set having one property has the other.
 +
 +
The least upper bound property is extremely important in calculus and analysis.  It is essential for many theorems, notably the ''[[mean value theorem]]'' and the ''intermediate value theorem''.
 +
 +
::''The rational numbers do not satisfy the least upper bound property.''
 +
 +
For example, if we can only use rational numbers, the set of numbers that have squares less than 2 has no rational least upper bound.  1.4142136 is an upper bound, but 1.41421357 is a smaller one.  The exact square root of 2 is the least upper bound that we need, but it isn't rational.
 +
 +
==Two ways to define the reals formally==
 +
There are two ways of formally constructing the reals from the rationals.  The simpler way is as [[Dedekind cut]]s, which see.  A Dedekind cut could be thought of as a formal least upper bound.  That is, the real number <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is, in effect, '''defined''' as "the least upper bound of the set of numbers whose squares are less than 2".
 +
:(This is a common motif in theoretical mathematics&mdash;you define something as the abstract set of things that have the properties that you want, and then show that they obey all the familiar properties of the original set.)
 +
The set thus created is "Dedekind complete", which is the same as having the least upper bound and greatest lower bound properties.
 +
 +
The second way is as [[Cauchy sequence]]s, which see.  The rationals are not "metrically complete" or "Cauchy complete", in that Cauchy sequences do not necessarily converge.  The reals can be, in effect, '''defined''' as "the things that Cauchy sequences would converge to".
 +
 +
The reals are both Dedekind complete and metrically complete.  The rationals are neither.  (In general, the two properties are not the same&mdash;the complex numbers are metrically complete but not Dedekind complete.)
  
 
==Infinity==
 
==Infinity==
  
The real numbers ''do not'' include <math>\infty</math> or <math>-\infty</math> (infinity and minus infinity).  However, there are non-standard models of real numbers which include <math>\infty</math> or include both <math>\infty</math> and <math>-\infty</math>.
+
The real numbers ''do not'' include [[infinity]]Every real number is finite, though the set of reals is an infinite set.
 +
 
 +
::'''INFINITY IS NOT A NUMBER!'''
 +
 
 +
However, there are non-standard models of real numbers which include <math>\infty</math> or include both <math>\infty</math> and <math>-\infty</math>.
 +
 
 +
There is no largest real number, because you can always make a real number larger by adding 1 (or 137.035 or 6.023&middot;10<sup>23</sup>) to it, and, similarly, no smallest real number.
 +
 
 +
<!-- [This paragraph is all wrong, and doesn't belong here in any case.  The topic should be covered in the compter arithmetic page, perhaps pointing here.] It is sometimes convenient to have a set of numbers that ''does'' include infinity. For example, in computer programming, "real arithmetic" is often done by a specific system defined by standard IEEE 754-1985; this system is built in to modern processor chips. It provides for values which print out as INF and -INF and which participate in arithmetic as if they were numbers. Thus, division by zero, which was often an error that stopped calculation on older machines, can be a legal operation which simply produces a +INF or -INF result. The system of numbers implemented in IEEE 754 is known in mathematics as the "affinely extended real numbers."-->
 +
 
 +
==Topological properties==
  
There is no largest real number, because you can always make a real number larger by adding 1 (or 137.035 or 6.023&middot;10<sup>23</sup>) to it, and no smallest real number, because you can always make a real number smaller by subtracting from it.
+
{{Math-a}}
  
Every real number is finite. One way to see this is to observe that you cannot subtract infinity from itself&mdash;the result is indeterminate&mdash;but, for any real number '''''x,''''' then '''''x - x = 0''''', exactly.
+
In the field of [[topology]], an important difference between the rational and real numbers is that the rational numbers are "totally disconnected"<!--No wikilink; I doubt that it would ever change color from red.-->, whereas the real numbers are [[connected (topology)|connected]]. To see this, observe that the set of numbers strictly less than <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is open in both sets, but it is also closed in the rationals but not in the reals.  In each case, it has a [[limit point]], namely, <math>\sqrt{2}</math>, which it clearly does not contain.  In the reals, the fact that <math>\sqrt{2}</math> is not contained makes the set not closed, whereas in the rationals, it doesn't matter because that point doesn't exist.  In the rationals, the fact that the set is both open and closed makes it disconnected from its complement.  Any open set in the rationals contains situations like this, which makes the rationals totally disconnected.
  
It is sometimes convenient to have a set of numbers that ''does'' include infinity. For example, in computer programming, "real arithmetic" is often done by a specific system defined by standard IEEE 754-1985; this system is built in to modern processor chips. It provides for values which print out as INF and -INF and which participate in arithmetic as if they were numbers. Thus, division by zero, which was often an error that stopped calculation on older machines, can be a legal operation which simply produces a +INF or -INF result. The system of numbers implemented in IEEE 754 is known in mathematics as the "affinely extended real numbers."
+
The fact that the reals are topologically connected makes them the standard starting point for many topological topics, such as [[homotopy]], [[homology]], and [[manifold]]s.
  
 
==History==
 
==History==
Line 39: Line 88:
  
 
[[Category:Mathematics]]
 
[[Category:Mathematics]]
 +
[[Category:Calculus]]
 +
[[Category:Topology]]

Revision as of 15:38, August 15, 2016

This article/section deals with mathematical concepts appropriate for a student in mid to late high school.

The real numbers are a set of numbers with extremely important theoretical and practical properties. They can be considered to be the numbers used for ordinary measurement of physical things like length, area, weight, charge, etc. Mathematicians denote the set of real numbers with an ornate capital letter: . They are the 4th item in this hierarchy of types of numbers:

Real numbers are typically represented by a decimal (or any other base) representation, as in 3.1416. It can be shown that any decimal representation that either terminates or gets into an endless repeating pattern is rational. The other numbers are real numbers that are irrational. Examples are and . These decimal representations neither repeat nor terminate.

Formal definition

Formally, real numbers are defined as the unique field which is ordered, metrically complete, and Archimedean. The reals can be constructed from the rationals by means of Dedekind cuts or Cauchy sequences, as outlined below.

Real line

The real numbers can be thought of as a line, called the real line. Each real number represents a point on the real line. [1]

The real line is useful as a coordinate system for graphing functions. Thus, the x-axis and y-axis are both instances of the real line. The real line is the basis for geometric measurements, and more generally for ideas in metric topology.

What is the problem? Aren't rational numbers good enough?

Any real-world measurement that anyone could possibly make, one can make as accurately as one wants with rational numbers. For example, one can calculate the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter to within one part is a trillion using the number 3.1415926535898 ( itself is irrational.) Put another way, you never have to worry about the difference between the rationals and the reals in a lumber yard or a laboratory. The technical term that topologists use for this state of affairs is that the rationals are dense.

The shortcoming of the rationals, that is overcome by defining the reals, is a somewhat subtle theoretical point. The most direct example is that, if one lived in a world with only rational numbers, 2 has no square root, even though it obviously should have one.

One can easily prove that there is no rational number m/n such that (m/n)2 = 2. The factors of m2 all come in pairs, as do the factors of n2. But the factors of m2 must be the same as the factors of n2 except for a single extra factor of 2.

The theoretical property that the rational numbers lack is called the least upper bound property.

Definition: A number B is an upper bound for a set of numbers if no element of the set is greater than B. (There is also the notion of a lower bound.)

For example, 10 is an upper bound for the open interval . 7 is also an upper bound, as is 6. 5 is not. 2 is a lower bound.

Some sets do not have upper bounds. For example, all rational or real numbers, or all odd integers.

Definition: A number L is a least upper bound (often abbreviated "lub") if it is an upper bound and no other upper bound is smaller. (There is also the notion of a greatest lower bound, abbreviated "glb".) 6 is the lub of the open interval . 3 is its glb. 6 and 3 are also the lub and glb of the closed interval —the inclusion of the endpoints makes no difference.
The least upper bound is also sometimes called the "supremum", abbreviated "sup". The greatest lower bound is also sometimes called the "infimum", abbreviated "inf".

A set has the least upper bound property if every set that has an upper bound has a least upper bound. There is also a greatest lower bound property, and any reasonable set having one property has the other.

The least upper bound property is extremely important in calculus and analysis. It is essential for many theorems, notably the mean value theorem and the intermediate value theorem.

The rational numbers do not satisfy the least upper bound property.

For example, if we can only use rational numbers, the set of numbers that have squares less than 2 has no rational least upper bound. 1.4142136 is an upper bound, but 1.41421357 is a smaller one. The exact square root of 2 is the least upper bound that we need, but it isn't rational.

Two ways to define the reals formally

There are two ways of formally constructing the reals from the rationals. The simpler way is as Dedekind cuts, which see. A Dedekind cut could be thought of as a formal least upper bound. That is, the real number is, in effect, defined as "the least upper bound of the set of numbers whose squares are less than 2".

(This is a common motif in theoretical mathematics—you define something as the abstract set of things that have the properties that you want, and then show that they obey all the familiar properties of the original set.)

The set thus created is "Dedekind complete", which is the same as having the least upper bound and greatest lower bound properties.

The second way is as Cauchy sequences, which see. The rationals are not "metrically complete" or "Cauchy complete", in that Cauchy sequences do not necessarily converge. The reals can be, in effect, defined as "the things that Cauchy sequences would converge to".

The reals are both Dedekind complete and metrically complete. The rationals are neither. (In general, the two properties are not the same—the complex numbers are metrically complete but not Dedekind complete.)

Infinity

The real numbers do not include infinity. Every real number is finite, though the set of reals is an infinite set.

INFINITY IS NOT A NUMBER!

However, there are non-standard models of real numbers which include or include both and .

There is no largest real number, because you can always make a real number larger by adding 1 (or 137.035 or 6.023·1023) to it, and, similarly, no smallest real number.


Topological properties

This article/section deals with mathematical concepts appropriate for a student in late university or graduate level.

In the field of topology, an important difference between the rational and real numbers is that the rational numbers are "totally disconnected", whereas the real numbers are connected. To see this, observe that the set of numbers strictly less than is open in both sets, but it is also closed in the rationals but not in the reals. In each case, it has a limit point, namely, , which it clearly does not contain. In the reals, the fact that is not contained makes the set not closed, whereas in the rationals, it doesn't matter because that point doesn't exist. In the rationals, the fact that the set is both open and closed makes it disconnected from its complement. Any open set in the rationals contains situations like this, which makes the rationals totally disconnected.

The fact that the reals are topologically connected makes them the standard starting point for many topological topics, such as homotopy, homology, and manifolds.

History

The ancient Greek mathematicians (Archimedes, Euclid, Pappus, Pythagoras and Zeno) are perhaps the first people to have created the abstract notion of a "number" (a real number; not an integer) to represent a geometrical measurement. They developed the correspondence between numbers and measurements such as distances, areas, and angles. To honor Archimedes' contribution, real analysts have named a property of the real numbers the Archimedean property. Real analysis remained in geometry's shadow until the development of the subfield of calculus. This subject subsumed all geometry known at the time, creating the field of analytic geometry.

Notes and references