Difference between revisions of "Reductio Ad Absurdum"

From Conservapedia
Jump to: navigation, search
(mathiness++)
 
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Reductio ad absurdum''', also called [[proof]] by contradiction, is a method of mathematical proof.  It involves assuming the opposite of what one is trying to prove, and showing that this would lead to a contradiction. An example of this is [[Euclid]]'s proof of the infinitude of the [[Prime number|primes]].
+
'''Reductio ad absurdum''', also called [[proof]] by contradiction, is a method of mathematical proof.  It involves assuming the opposite of what one is trying to prove, and showing that this would lead to a contradiction. It works by the law of the excluded middle. The proof typically follows this structure:
 +
 
 +
#Create an initial assumption
 +
#Follow a series of axiomatically valid steps
 +
#Reach a contradiction
 +
#Therefore the initial assumption is incorrect
 +
 
 +
An example of this is [[Euclid]]'s proof of the infinitude of the [[Prime number|primes]]:
 +
 
 +
#Assume there are finitely many primes
 +
#Take the product of all primes and call it ''N''. Since ''N+1'' is not in our finite set of primes, it must be composite
 +
#By the [[fundamental theorem of arithmetic]], ''N+1'' has a prime factorization. But ''N+1'' is not divisible by any of the previous primes
 +
#Since ''N+1'' is composite, there must be a prime missing from our set of primes. But this set contains all primes
 +
#Therefore, our initial assumption ("there are finitely many primes") is invalid
  
 
[[Category:Mathematics]]
 
[[Category:Mathematics]]

Revision as of 16:28, June 30, 2008

Reductio ad absurdum, also called proof by contradiction, is a method of mathematical proof. It involves assuming the opposite of what one is trying to prove, and showing that this would lead to a contradiction. It works by the law of the excluded middle. The proof typically follows this structure:

  1. Create an initial assumption
  2. Follow a series of axiomatically valid steps
  3. Reach a contradiction
  4. Therefore the initial assumption is incorrect

An example of this is Euclid's proof of the infinitude of the primes:

  1. Assume there are finitely many primes
  2. Take the product of all primes and call it N. Since N+1 is not in our finite set of primes, it must be composite
  3. By the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, N+1 has a prime factorization. But N+1 is not divisible by any of the previous primes
  4. Since N+1 is composite, there must be a prime missing from our set of primes. But this set contains all primes
  5. Therefore, our initial assumption ("there are finitely many primes") is invalid