Difference between revisions of "Ontological argument"

From Conservapedia
Jump to: navigation, search
(Counter-criticism: Incoherent.)
(red link turned blue)
(2 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 21: Line 21:
 
[[Kant]] weighed in against Descartes' version, challenging the premise that existence is a predicate of perfection. Kant said he could imagine a hundred thalers (coins) in such great detail that whether or not they actually existed was arbitrary, as there was no difference other than this between the imagined and the existent thalers.  
 
[[Kant]] weighed in against Descartes' version, challenging the premise that existence is a predicate of perfection. Kant said he could imagine a hundred thalers (coins) in such great detail that whether or not they actually existed was arbitrary, as there was no difference other than this between the imagined and the existent thalers.  
  
[[Davies]] insisted that Anselm's argument [[begs the question]]- it assumes what it sets out to prove. In other words, if a God existed, he would be supremely perfect, and would therefore exist. In explicit form, the first might be construed to mean 'The concept of God is the most supremely perfect concept'. It has been suggested that the ontological argument is therefore [[flawed]] in that it uses [[equivocation]] to progress from a [[concept of God]] to an existent of God to an existent God, and flawed in that the entire argument collapses irreparably once this is exposed.
+
[[Davies]] insisted that Anselm's argument [[begs the question]]- it assumes what it sets out to prove. In other words, if a God existed, he would be supremely perfect, and would therefore exist. In explicit form, the first might be construed to mean 'The concept of God is the most supremely perfect concept'. It has been suggested that the ontological argument is therefore [[fatally flawed|flawed]] in that it uses [[equivocation]] to progress from a [[concept of God]] to property of God to an [[God|existent God]], and flawed in that the entire argument collapses irreparably once this is exposed.
  
 
== Notes ==
 
== Notes ==
Line 28: Line 28:
 
[[Category: Arguments for the existence of God]]
 
[[Category: Arguments for the existence of God]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 +
 +
==Further Reading==
 +
[[Essay: Why Is There Something Rather Than Nothing?]]
 +
 +
[[Essay: One person's view of the Ontological Argument]]

Revision as of 04:19, April 11, 2013

Anselm of Canterbury was the originator of the ontological argument

According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, "Ontological arguments are arguments, for the conclusion that God exists, from premises which are supposed to derive from some source other than observation of the world — e.g., from reason alone."[1] Anselm of Canterbury's ontological argument uses the definition of God to prove His existence. Anselm's ontological argument remained influential for centuries, and was later used by Descartes. Anselm's proof is as follows:

God is that for which no greater being is conceivable.
That which exists is greater than that which does not exist.
That which does not exist fails to satisfy the definition of God.
Therefore God exists.

In a sense this proof of the existence of God is similar to the mathematical proofs based on deriving a contradiction of something is not true. Accepting the definition of God, as most would, while then denying that God exists leads to a contradiction as existence is a necessary element of perfection in this context.

Recent Ontological Arguments

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states the following regarding recent developments in ontological arguments for the existence of God:

In more recent times, Kurt Gödel, Charles Hartshorne, Norman Malcolm and Alvin Plantinga have all presented much-discussed ontological arguments which bear interesting connections to the earlier arguments of St. Anselm, Descartes and Leibniz. Of these, the most interesting are those of Gödel and Plantinga; in these cases, however, it is unclear whether we should really say that these authors claim that the arguments are proofs of the existence of God.[2]

Criticism

Gaunilo, a contemporary of Anselm, played devil's advocate by using reductio ad absurdum and envisaged a 'lost, yet most perfect island'. Gaunilo argued that just because we can imagine this island does not mean it actually exists. Anselm responded by arguing that such an island is not instrinsically necessary to existence because the concept of no greater conceivable being existing would only apply to God, not to something tangible such as an island.

Kant weighed in against Descartes' version, challenging the premise that existence is a predicate of perfection. Kant said he could imagine a hundred thalers (coins) in such great detail that whether or not they actually existed was arbitrary, as there was no difference other than this between the imagined and the existent thalers.

Davies insisted that Anselm's argument begs the question- it assumes what it sets out to prove. In other words, if a God existed, he would be supremely perfect, and would therefore exist. In explicit form, the first might be construed to mean 'The concept of God is the most supremely perfect concept'. It has been suggested that the ontological argument is therefore flawed in that it uses equivocation to progress from a concept of God to property of God to an existent God, and flawed in that the entire argument collapses irreparably once this is exposed.

Notes

Further Reading

Essay: Why Is There Something Rather Than Nothing?

Essay: One person's view of the Ontological Argument