Changes

Morality

8,147 bytes added, 12:47, March 31, 2007
Morality It is a system of values placed upon certain actions necessary at the outset to distinguish between morality and opinionsethics, terms not seldom employed synonymously. An example would be that some people think that the marriage of a man Morality is antecedent to another man ethics: it denotes those concrete activities of which ethics is moral based on the principles of utilitarianismscience. However, others think that such a thing It may be defined as human conduct in so far as it is immoral. Some people believe that marriage freely subordinated to the ideal of any sort what is amoral(without morality). Therefore, these people would have differing moral codesright and fitting.
Some biologists argue that This ideal governing our free actions is common to the human race. Though there is wide divergence as to theories of ethics [[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/05556a.htm]] , there is a fundamental agreement among men regarding the general lines of conduct desirable in public and private life. Thus Mr. L. T. Hobhouse has well said: <blockquote>"The comparative study of ethics, which is apt in its earlier stages to impress the student with a bewildering sense of the diversity of moral judgments, ends rather by impressing them with a more fundamental and far-reaching uniformity. Through the greatest extent of time and space over which we have records, we find a recurrence of the common features of ordinary morality grew , which to my mind at least is not less impressive than the variations which also appear".</blockquote> Many secular writers and scholars say a clear and decent moral philosophy may be and has been developed without recourse to mysticism, as religion is. There is no way to prove, objectively, that any religion is truer than any other. On the other hand, basing a moral philosophy on duty, loyalty, and “women and children first” can produce, and has produced, a set of principles for living a just and proper life that does not require a belief in a deity or other prop outside of recognition of human fellowship. It should be noted that the western world's first examples of philosophy, in the Greek city states, did in fact arise out of behavioral rules shaped by evolutiontheir religious beliefs. They see social behaviors displayed by some primates Both Plato and Aristotle acknowledged a single Divine source as the precursors origin of the cosmos and, ipso facto, the origin of being or existence itself. Plato specifically believed in the immortality of the human soul, not as a matter of mysticism, but as developed in philosophical logic. This appears most clearly in his dialog, the "Phaedo," [[http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/phaedo.html]] in which Socrates's sorrowful friends visit him in prison, just as he is about to drink the hemlock poison. He comforts them with the certainty that his soul is about to pass over into a new realm. One of the charges upon which he was condemned to death by the Athenian Assembly was leading the youth astray from the many, syncretistic gods brought into cosmopolitan Athens via the city's vast foreign trade. Plato, using the voice of Socrates, argued that there is only a single Divinity, and that Divinity is the source of moral understanding. The whole of Plato's "Republic" is aimed at the concept that a just society must begin with this moral understanding and rest upon the moralityof its rulers. They cite examples Roughly 400 years earlier the Old Testament prophets Amos, Hosea, Isaiah, and Jeremiah had repeatedly admonished the people of both kingdoms of Israel with the same message. Secularists start with the assumption that concepts such as rhesus monkeys whichduty, when given loyalty, and “women and children first” already exist as the foundation blocks for constructing a chance set of moral principles that will be independent of a belief in a deity. But, where did they come from? Again, in historical fact, those basic concepts – duty, loyalty, and “women and children first” – all arose under political regimes rooted in religious beliefs. It was in those codes that the earliest known statements of such basic principles occurred. Every code of law in the western world, such as Hammurabi's Code [[http://www.wsu.edu/~dee/MESO/CODE.HTM]] from around 1770 BC, has predicated the official state god as its source of legitimacy. Around 1500 BC, Moses in the same way transmitted the Ten Commandments from God to get food the Israelite people. In every case the formulaic structure is the same. The ruler or spiritual leader rules by pulling the power and grace of God, and the ruler's law code is always seen as bringing God's moral justice to his people. Why should this be uniformly the case? Eric Voegelin and Friedrich Hayek provide an understanding. Eric Voegelin, covers this question in magisterial fashion in "Israel and Revelation," one of the five volumes in his "Order and History." Dr. Voegelin notes that religion and morality are not "things" or "objects" that a chain single person, or a committee of intellectuals, sat down and conjured up during a conference meeting. He found it necessary to make this reality clear, in distinction to the modern-day, liberal-socialist view that delivers societies and their political structure are simply "on the spot" creations of the minds of morally relativistic human intellectuals. That misconception, for example, is the root of the disastrous savagery produced by the French Revolutionary intellectuals' "ideas" about a shock perfect socialistic government. As present-day French intellectual André Maurois observed in his "A History of France," the French intellectuals, unlike their English and American contemporaries, had never had so much as five minutes actual experience in self-government. In contrast, the English and their American political heirs had struggled for centuries to another monkeyhammer out their unwritten constitution governing the rights and privileges of individuals under law, have been known against the crown. Those political understandings were bound up in their religious understandings of the duty of sovereigns and subjects to starve God. No English king, or Continental sovereign, could claim legitimacy without the blessings of the Christian church. That is why Europe's first secular and imperialist ruler Napoleon ostentatiously snatched the crown from the hands of the the bishop and placed it himself upon his head at the coronation ceremony. Symbolically, this represented liberals' hubristic presumption that they alone are the rulers of the universe and that they need no help from God, socialistic, individual hubris that presumes to the capacity to make up its own rules of morality is a prescription for anarchic demise.   == Morality and the Law == Morality can be distinguished from law or from justice according to the way in which the latter is publicly enforced and sanctioned through the power of the state, while the former is regarded as a private matter where wrongs are to the moral discredit of a person but not such as to allow legal recourse for those wronged. Complaints are often made about the absence of such a distinction, that virtue or morality cannot be or ought not be legislated, or about its presence, that the decline of private morality calls for a public and legal remedy. The distinction is real enough, and its presence reveals another boundary between polynomic domains of value. The ultimate moral evaluation of an action concerns the intention. Many actions innocent in themselves may be immoral because of the motive. That motive may be difficult for other persons to know. It may even be impossible for others to know: thus the emphasis (as in the example cited by Jesus of adultery committed in the heart -- Matthew 5:27) is that morality is morality even if wrongs are known only to the agent (and to God). The moral sanction of religion, therefore, is a considerable timemuch different matter than the moral sanction of law.<ref> "Primates The right of privacy (and Philosophersthe right against self-incrimination, where a judicial wrong has been committed and the state must prove culpable motive) protects the individual's self-knowledge of motive from the law and the state. Individuals are properly at legal liberty to pursue actions that are not judicial wrongs for good reasons, bad reasons, or no reasons; and the morality of those actions is a private, personal matter, or a matter of interpersonal judgment on a level of " mere" morality.  The absence of a distinction between morality and justice is a kind of moralism. The principle that all moral wrongs should be legally sanctioned as judicial wrongs, erasing the distinction between morality and justice, may be called judicial moralism. Usually this means generalizing the morality of intention into the morality of action rather than the opposite, which would simply evaluate actions as right or wrong, without qualifying the judgment by Frans de Waal<any consideration of motive or intention: although this does happen in tort law it is called "strict liability," and some legal scholars, including Richard Epstein [[http:/ref> /www.friesian.com/chicago.htm]], believe all torts should be interpreted according to strict liability. However, strict liability would also make things much easier for prosecutors in criminal cases, and it is now becoming common for laws to be passed that ignore motives and intentions (the mens rea). Thus, "money laundering" laws, which require reporting to the government the transfers of certain amounts of cash or bearer financial instruments, although supposedly written to catch drug dealers and their agents, are typically enforced against innocent people who are either ignorant of such an obscure law or who do not believe their financial privacy in the course of innocent transactions is any of the government's business. But it doesn't matter how innocent the money or the motives are. This trend in criminal law is, of course, tyranny and injustice.
Dr Frans de Waal argues that primates are social animals, and must constrain their behavior in order to live in a group. He maintains that these constraints have shaped behaviors from which human morality has emerged. He does not assert that chimpanzees are moral, but argues that emotional bases that can be observed among primates are the foundation for the evolution of human morality.
He points to the display of both empathy and self-awareness among apes, and asserts that human morality begins with a similar concern for others and the understanding of social rules about the treatment of others. <ref>[http://www.nytimes.com/2007/03/20/science/20moral.html?pagewanted=1&ei=5124&en=84f902c89c5a9173&ex=1332043200&partner=permalink&exprod=permalink]</ref>
== References ==
<references/>
Cathrein, Religion und Moral (Freiburg, 1900); Fox, Religion and Morality (New York, 1899); Devas, Key to the World's Progress (London, 1906); Idem, Studies of Family Life (London, 1886); Balfour, Foundations of Belief (London, 1895), Part I, i; Catholic Truth Society's Lectures on the History of Religions (London, 1910);Laws of Justice, Hammurabi;
NsTeam1RO, nsTeam1RW, nsTeam1_talkRO, nsTeam1_talkRW
26,487
edits